SlideShare une entreprise Scribd logo
1  sur  4
Télécharger pour lire hors ligne
Interdisciplinary, unpaid research opportunities are available. Various academic specialties are required. If interested, email me at
dr.freedom@hotmail.ca.
An Ethical Analysis of Forcible Humanitarian Intervention
By Oleg Nekrassovski
Forcible humanitarian intervention is a military intervention, which interferes coercively
in the domestic affairs of another state for the purpose of reducing the suffering of some or all
people within that state’s borders. The legality as well as the morality of forcible humanitarian
intervention is disputed because the modern international society is built on principles of
sovereignty, non-intervention, and the non-use of force (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). In fact, in
order to protect state sovereignty, international law traditionally prohibited states from
interfering into each other’s internal affairs, especially with military force (Feinstein and
Slaughter, 2004). The present paper will assess and counter the arguments against legitimizing
the practice of forcible humanitarian intervention. In particular, it will be argued that it is our
moral duty to stop a humanitarian crisis in another country; state leaders have every moral
right to risk the lives of their military personnel to stop a humanitarian crisis in another country,
if this risk and especially the collateral damage caused by the intervention will be outweighed
by the total reduction in human suffering that it brings about; if forcible humanitarian
intervention is legitimized, subject to such rules and restrictions, there is little need to fear that
this right will be abused; the fact that states may only engage in humanitarian interventions in
order to promote their national interest, is a misguided objection to legitimizing forcible
humanitarian intervention.
One argument against legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention states that any
violation of human rights (for example), within a particular state, is a problem, the
responsibility for fixing which falls solely on the shoulders of that state’s citizens and political
leaders. Outsiders have no moral duty to intervene even if they can fix it (Bellamy and Wheeler,
2011). This moral argument does not seem to be particularly convincing, as it suggests that
altruism is not a positive moral value. In fact, according to classical utilitarianism, the morally
right thing to always do is to seek to bring welfare or happiness to the greatest number of
people (Heinze, 2005). Consequently, if there is a humanitarian crisis in a particular state and
we can stop it by forcibly intervening, than it is our moral duty to do so.
Another argument against legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention, argues that
state leaders do not have the moral right to risk the lives of their military personnel merely in
order to reduce human suffering (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). Or as Samuel P. Huntington put
it, more bluntly, in reference to a specific case of a forcible humanitarian intervention: “it is
morally unjustifiable and politically indefensible that members of the [U.S.] armed forces
should be killed to prevent Somalis from killing one another” (Smith, 1998). However,
Huntington has not usually been known to be a moralist (Smith, 1998), and Smith (1998)
himself does not find this argument convincing; nor does the author of the present paper.
Interdisciplinary, unpaid research opportunities are available. Various academic specialties are required. If interested, email me at
dr.freedom@hotmail.ca.
After all, state leaders have the moral right to sacrifice the lives of their military
personnel in order to protect their country from foreign threats – a practice which solely
benefits the state’s leaders (in terms of greater public support, etc.) and citizens (in terms of
greater security), and hence is completely selfish, at least from the point of view of citizens of
other nations. On the other hand, societies that allow their leaders to risk the lives of their
military personnel in order to reduce human suffering in foreign lands are far more altruistic,
and hence morally superior, than those societies that do not allow such a practice. Moreover,
military personnel who have joined the armed forces voluntary (as tends to be the case for
most armed forces that take part in forcible humanitarian interventions) have consented to any
and all risk to their lives that may come from their service in the military. Hence, it is unclear
how risking their lives can be immoral.
Also, according to utilitarianism, the morally right thing to do is any action that will lead
to the greatest total amount of happiness or welfare. Hence, it is permissible to reduce the
welfare of some people if these actions will lead to a proportionate, per person increase in
welfare of a larger number of other people (Heinze, 2005). Hence, state leaders have every
moral right to risk the lives of their military personnel for the sake of a humanitarian
intervention, if they are confident that the total human suffering incurred in the process will be
outweighed by the total reduction in human suffering that this intervention will bring.
But how can states, that may want to intervene, be reasonably sure that they do more
good than harm? After all, forcible humanitarian intervention is similar to a military attack;
hence it is inevitable that it will harm and even kill some innocent people in the process
(Heinze, 2005). Consequently, a humanitarian intervention should only be permissible when
there are sufficiently large scale abuses of people that result in sufficiently severe suffering (e.
g. large scale massacre, genocide, or ethnic cleansing). While it would not make any
humanitarian sense to attempt deposing a regime which engages in “smaller-scale or less
severe abuses such as political repression and intimidation” (Heinze, 2005).
Also, along the same lines, it is important to note that the state or an international
organization, which is considering a specific, forcible humanitarian intervention, must have
sufficient military capabilities (and be willing to use them for this intervention) to easily
overpower any military opposition that its intervention may encounter in that specific case
(Heinze, 2005). If this is not so, and the intervening force is likely to be defeated, than the
intervention will only create more suffering for the citizens of the country in a humanitarian
crisis and the members of the intervening force. But even if the interveners are likely to win,
but the opponent is too strong, intervening would still be unreasonable because a powerful
military opposition is likely to lead to great destruction, and hence, more harm than good
(Heinze, 2005).
All of the above considerations for a morally justifiable intervention are confirmed by
the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS), according to which
Interdisciplinary, unpaid research opportunities are available. Various academic specialties are required. If interested, email me at
dr.freedom@hotmail.ca.
forcible humanitarian intervention should only take place when a large-scale loss of life or
ethnic cleansing are taking place or are anticipated (Weiss, 2004). Moreover, such an
intervention should have ‘right’ intentions, be done only as a last resort, should use
proportional means, and have reasonable prospects of success. Finally, for the sake of greater
neutrality, the Security Council of the United Nations should be the preferred decision maker in
such cases (Weiss, 2004).
According to Realists, states only act out of selfish motives. Hence, it is argued that
there is a risk that if forcible humanitarian intervention is legitimized, states will start using the
right to engage in humanitarian interventions as an excuse and a convenient, noble-sounding
cover for engaging in additional selfish pursuits of national interest. In other words, the right to
engage in humanitarian interventions is open to abuse (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). However,
given the rules, described above, for distinguishing between morally justifiable and unjustifiable
humanitarian interventions, only those humanitarian interventions that follow such rules can
be legitimized and all the others forbidden, making it hard, if not impossible, to abuse the right
to engage in humanitarian intervention. Moreover, there is little reason to believe that all
humanitarian interventions that do happen, are done out of selfish motives. Sometimes states
engage in forcible humanitarian interventions out of a combination of a desire to appease the
humanitarian sentiments of domestic publics and some genuine moral concerns (Bellamy and
Wheeler, 2011).
Also, it is argued that because states act only in order to pursue national interest, they
engage in humanitarian interventions only, or at least primarily, when they believe that their
national interest is at stake. This practice of selecting which humanitarian crises to solve
through intervention, based on national interests rather than moral concerns, is deemed as
being immoral by its opponents (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). Though this practice may indeed
be immoral, it is unclear how it can be used as an objection to legitimizing humanitarian
intervention. First, because the resources of all states are limited, it would be unrealistic to
expect even a hypothetical, morally pure state to attempt to solve all humanitarian crises that
arise around the world. Second, even a hypothetical state with unlimited resources, which
engages only in those humanitarian interventions which benefit its national interest, still
reduces some human suffering in the world. While preventing such a state from engaging in any
humanitarian intervention, will mean that it will not be reducing any human suffering at all.
Thus, we have seen that intervening into the affairs of another state, in order to solve a
humanitarian crisis, is a morally right thing to do. Also, there are several reasons why state
leaders have a moral right to risk the lives of their military personnel in order to reduce human
suffering in another country. However, forcible humanitarian intervention is only justified when
the human suffering, which it will inevitably bring about as a side effect, is smaller than the
total amount of human suffering that it will eliminate. This can happen only when the
humanitarian crisis is sufficiently severe and when the intervening forces will easily overpower
Interdisciplinary, unpaid research opportunities are available. Various academic specialties are required. If interested, email me at
dr.freedom@hotmail.ca.
all military opposition. Hence, legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention, subject to these
and related rules and restrictions, greatly reduces the risk of this right being abused. Finally,
there are several reasons why the fact that states may only engage in humanitarian
interventions in order to promote their national interest, is a misguided objection to
legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention.
References
Bellamy, A. and Wheeler, N. (2011). “Humanitarian Intervention in World Politics.” In J. Baylis,
S. Smith and P. Owens (Eds.), Globalization of World Politics 5th
Edition. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Feinstein, L. and Slaughter, A.M. (2004). “A Duty to Prevent.” Foreign Affairs. Vol. 83(1), p. 136-
150.
Heinz, E. A. (2005). “Commonsense Morality and the Consequentialist Ethics of Humanitarian
Intervention.” Journal of Military Ethics. Vol. 4(3), p. 168-182.
Smith, M. (1998). “Humanitarian Intervention: An Overview of the Ethical Issues.” Ethics and
International Affairs. Vol. 12, p. 63-79.
Weiss, T. G. (2004). “The Sunset of Humanitarian Intervention: The Responsibility to Protect in a
Unipolar Era.” Security Dialogue. Vol. 35(2), p. 135-153.

Contenu connexe

En vedette

Fixing the Broken Promise of Education for All
Fixing the Broken Promise of Education for AllFixing the Broken Promise of Education for All
Fixing the Broken Promise of Education for AllUNICEF Publications
 
Tipi di impianti fotovoltaici
Tipi di impianti fotovoltaiciTipi di impianti fotovoltaici
Tipi di impianti fotovoltaiciDigital Bridge
 
Evaluating a Humanitarian Action Proposal
Evaluating a Humanitarian Action ProposalEvaluating a Humanitarian Action Proposal
Evaluating a Humanitarian Action ProposalShakeb Nabi
 
New approaches to humanitarianism
New approaches to humanitarianismNew approaches to humanitarianism
New approaches to humanitarianismHelen Hintjens
 
Humanitarianism and volunteerism
Humanitarianism and volunteerismHumanitarianism and volunteerism
Humanitarianism and volunteerismDavid Hii
 
Solitary Confinement, A violation of Human Rights ppt
Solitary Confinement, A violation of Human Rights pptSolitary Confinement, A violation of Human Rights ppt
Solitary Confinement, A violation of Human Rights pptMukesh Vashisht
 
International humanitarian law presentation
International humanitarian law   presentationInternational humanitarian law   presentation
International humanitarian law presentationRida Khan
 
what3words brochure | Humanitarian
what3words brochure | Humanitarianwhat3words brochure | Humanitarian
what3words brochure | Humanitarianwhat3words
 
International humanitarian law (ihl)
International humanitarian law  (ihl)International humanitarian law  (ihl)
International humanitarian law (ihl)bhagya913
 
Humanitarian Action for Children 2014
Humanitarian Action for Children 2014Humanitarian Action for Children 2014
Humanitarian Action for Children 2014UNICEF Publications
 

En vedette (17)

Humanitarian Law
Humanitarian LawHumanitarian Law
Humanitarian Law
 
Fixing the Broken Promise of Education for All
Fixing the Broken Promise of Education for AllFixing the Broken Promise of Education for All
Fixing the Broken Promise of Education for All
 
Tipi di impianti fotovoltaici
Tipi di impianti fotovoltaiciTipi di impianti fotovoltaici
Tipi di impianti fotovoltaici
 
Health and Safety on Mission: Mitigating Safety Risks: A Personal and Profess...
Health and Safety on Mission: Mitigating Safety Risks: A Personal and Profess...Health and Safety on Mission: Mitigating Safety Risks: A Personal and Profess...
Health and Safety on Mission: Mitigating Safety Risks: A Personal and Profess...
 
Evaluating a Humanitarian Action Proposal
Evaluating a Humanitarian Action ProposalEvaluating a Humanitarian Action Proposal
Evaluating a Humanitarian Action Proposal
 
New approaches to humanitarianism
New approaches to humanitarianismNew approaches to humanitarianism
New approaches to humanitarianism
 
wfp268240
wfp268240wfp268240
wfp268240
 
Humanitarian Innovation
Humanitarian InnovationHumanitarian Innovation
Humanitarian Innovation
 
Humanitarianism and volunteerism
Humanitarianism and volunteerismHumanitarianism and volunteerism
Humanitarianism and volunteerism
 
Solitary Confinement, A violation of Human Rights ppt
Solitary Confinement, A violation of Human Rights pptSolitary Confinement, A violation of Human Rights ppt
Solitary Confinement, A violation of Human Rights ppt
 
International humanitarian law presentation
International humanitarian law   presentationInternational humanitarian law   presentation
International humanitarian law presentation
 
what3words brochure | Humanitarian
what3words brochure | Humanitarianwhat3words brochure | Humanitarian
what3words brochure | Humanitarian
 
International humanitarian law (ihl)
International humanitarian law  (ihl)International humanitarian law  (ihl)
International humanitarian law (ihl)
 
International Humanitarian Law
International Humanitarian LawInternational Humanitarian Law
International Humanitarian Law
 
Humanitarian Action for Children 2014
Humanitarian Action for Children 2014Humanitarian Action for Children 2014
Humanitarian Action for Children 2014
 
Project report ISR
Project report ISRProject report ISR
Project report ISR
 
Disaster ppt
Disaster pptDisaster ppt
Disaster ppt
 

Plus de Oleg Nekrassovski

Psychopathy - Brief Overview of Its Behavioral, Experimental, and Neural Aspects
Psychopathy - Brief Overview of Its Behavioral, Experimental, and Neural AspectsPsychopathy - Brief Overview of Its Behavioral, Experimental, and Neural Aspects
Psychopathy - Brief Overview of Its Behavioral, Experimental, and Neural AspectsOleg Nekrassovski
 
Californian vs. Federal Marijuana Laws, and Healthcare
Californian vs. Federal Marijuana Laws, and HealthcareCalifornian vs. Federal Marijuana Laws, and Healthcare
Californian vs. Federal Marijuana Laws, and HealthcareOleg Nekrassovski
 
Details and Implementation Plan of a Code of Ethics for a Proposed Lunar Colony
Details and Implementation Plan of a Code of Ethics for a Proposed Lunar ColonyDetails and Implementation Plan of a Code of Ethics for a Proposed Lunar Colony
Details and Implementation Plan of a Code of Ethics for a Proposed Lunar ColonyOleg Nekrassovski
 
The Politics of Gender, Sexual Orientation, and the Canadian Forces, between ...
The Politics of Gender, Sexual Orientation, and the Canadian Forces, between ...The Politics of Gender, Sexual Orientation, and the Canadian Forces, between ...
The Politics of Gender, Sexual Orientation, and the Canadian Forces, between ...Oleg Nekrassovski
 
Learning, Insight, and Innovation in Animals in the Context of Evolution
Learning, Insight, and Innovation in Animals in the Context of EvolutionLearning, Insight, and Innovation in Animals in the Context of Evolution
Learning, Insight, and Innovation in Animals in the Context of EvolutionOleg Nekrassovski
 
Corporate Psychopaths: The Good, the Evil, and Organizational Differences
Corporate Psychopaths: The Good, the Evil, and Organizational DifferencesCorporate Psychopaths: The Good, the Evil, and Organizational Differences
Corporate Psychopaths: The Good, the Evil, and Organizational DifferencesOleg Nekrassovski
 
Transformational Leadership, Servant Leadership, and Psychological Needs
Transformational Leadership, Servant Leadership, and Psychological NeedsTransformational Leadership, Servant Leadership, and Psychological Needs
Transformational Leadership, Servant Leadership, and Psychological NeedsOleg Nekrassovski
 
Leadership and Organizational Function
Leadership and Organizational FunctionLeadership and Organizational Function
Leadership and Organizational FunctionOleg Nekrassovski
 
Review of Andrew J. Bacevich's The New American Militarism - How Americans ar...
Review of Andrew J. Bacevich's The New American Militarism - How Americans ar...Review of Andrew J. Bacevich's The New American Militarism - How Americans ar...
Review of Andrew J. Bacevich's The New American Militarism - How Americans ar...Oleg Nekrassovski
 
Review of 2 Journal Articles on Psychological Factors Influencing Capital Pun...
Review of 2 Journal Articles on Psychological Factors Influencing Capital Pun...Review of 2 Journal Articles on Psychological Factors Influencing Capital Pun...
Review of 2 Journal Articles on Psychological Factors Influencing Capital Pun...Oleg Nekrassovski
 
NASA and the Space Shuttle Program
NASA and the Space Shuttle ProgramNASA and the Space Shuttle Program
NASA and the Space Shuttle ProgramOleg Nekrassovski
 
NASA - The Quest for the Moon
NASA - The Quest for the MoonNASA - The Quest for the Moon
NASA - The Quest for the MoonOleg Nekrassovski
 
Canada, and the US Ballistic Missile Defence Program
Canada, and the US Ballistic Missile Defence ProgramCanada, and the US Ballistic Missile Defence Program
Canada, and the US Ballistic Missile Defence ProgramOleg Nekrassovski
 
Barriers to International Cooperation
Barriers to International CooperationBarriers to International Cooperation
Barriers to International CooperationOleg Nekrassovski
 
Econometric Military Production Function
Econometric Military Production FunctionEconometric Military Production Function
Econometric Military Production FunctionOleg Nekrassovski
 
Canada’s Commitment to Tolerance, Democracy, and the Rule of Law
Canada’s Commitment to Tolerance, Democracy, and the Rule of LawCanada’s Commitment to Tolerance, Democracy, and the Rule of Law
Canada’s Commitment to Tolerance, Democracy, and the Rule of LawOleg Nekrassovski
 

Plus de Oleg Nekrassovski (20)

Psychopathy - Brief Overview of Its Behavioral, Experimental, and Neural Aspects
Psychopathy - Brief Overview of Its Behavioral, Experimental, and Neural AspectsPsychopathy - Brief Overview of Its Behavioral, Experimental, and Neural Aspects
Psychopathy - Brief Overview of Its Behavioral, Experimental, and Neural Aspects
 
Psychopathy and Leadership
Psychopathy and LeadershipPsychopathy and Leadership
Psychopathy and Leadership
 
Californian vs. Federal Marijuana Laws, and Healthcare
Californian vs. Federal Marijuana Laws, and HealthcareCalifornian vs. Federal Marijuana Laws, and Healthcare
Californian vs. Federal Marijuana Laws, and Healthcare
 
Details and Implementation Plan of a Code of Ethics for a Proposed Lunar Colony
Details and Implementation Plan of a Code of Ethics for a Proposed Lunar ColonyDetails and Implementation Plan of a Code of Ethics for a Proposed Lunar Colony
Details and Implementation Plan of a Code of Ethics for a Proposed Lunar Colony
 
The Politics of Gender, Sexual Orientation, and the Canadian Forces, between ...
The Politics of Gender, Sexual Orientation, and the Canadian Forces, between ...The Politics of Gender, Sexual Orientation, and the Canadian Forces, between ...
The Politics of Gender, Sexual Orientation, and the Canadian Forces, between ...
 
Learning, Insight, and Innovation in Animals in the Context of Evolution
Learning, Insight, and Innovation in Animals in the Context of EvolutionLearning, Insight, and Innovation in Animals in the Context of Evolution
Learning, Insight, and Innovation in Animals in the Context of Evolution
 
Corporate Psychopaths: The Good, the Evil, and Organizational Differences
Corporate Psychopaths: The Good, the Evil, and Organizational DifferencesCorporate Psychopaths: The Good, the Evil, and Organizational Differences
Corporate Psychopaths: The Good, the Evil, and Organizational Differences
 
Transformational Leadership, Servant Leadership, and Psychological Needs
Transformational Leadership, Servant Leadership, and Psychological NeedsTransformational Leadership, Servant Leadership, and Psychological Needs
Transformational Leadership, Servant Leadership, and Psychological Needs
 
Leadership and Organizational Function
Leadership and Organizational FunctionLeadership and Organizational Function
Leadership and Organizational Function
 
Review of Andrew J. Bacevich's The New American Militarism - How Americans ar...
Review of Andrew J. Bacevich's The New American Militarism - How Americans ar...Review of Andrew J. Bacevich's The New American Militarism - How Americans ar...
Review of Andrew J. Bacevich's The New American Militarism - How Americans ar...
 
Review of 2 Journal Articles on Psychological Factors Influencing Capital Pun...
Review of 2 Journal Articles on Psychological Factors Influencing Capital Pun...Review of 2 Journal Articles on Psychological Factors Influencing Capital Pun...
Review of 2 Journal Articles on Psychological Factors Influencing Capital Pun...
 
Premenstrual Syndrome (PMS)
Premenstrual Syndrome (PMS)Premenstrual Syndrome (PMS)
Premenstrual Syndrome (PMS)
 
NASA and the Space Shuttle Program
NASA and the Space Shuttle ProgramNASA and the Space Shuttle Program
NASA and the Space Shuttle Program
 
NASA - The Quest for the Moon
NASA - The Quest for the MoonNASA - The Quest for the Moon
NASA - The Quest for the Moon
 
Canada, and the US Ballistic Missile Defence Program
Canada, and the US Ballistic Missile Defence ProgramCanada, and the US Ballistic Missile Defence Program
Canada, and the US Ballistic Missile Defence Program
 
Barriers to International Cooperation
Barriers to International CooperationBarriers to International Cooperation
Barriers to International Cooperation
 
Econometric Military Production Function
Econometric Military Production FunctionEconometric Military Production Function
Econometric Military Production Function
 
Separatism in Quebec
Separatism in QuebecSeparatism in Quebec
Separatism in Quebec
 
Food Subsidies and Canada
Food Subsidies and CanadaFood Subsidies and Canada
Food Subsidies and Canada
 
Canada’s Commitment to Tolerance, Democracy, and the Rule of Law
Canada’s Commitment to Tolerance, Democracy, and the Rule of LawCanada’s Commitment to Tolerance, Democracy, and the Rule of Law
Canada’s Commitment to Tolerance, Democracy, and the Rule of Law
 

An Ethical Analysis of Forcible Humanitarian Intervention

  • 1. Interdisciplinary, unpaid research opportunities are available. Various academic specialties are required. If interested, email me at dr.freedom@hotmail.ca. An Ethical Analysis of Forcible Humanitarian Intervention By Oleg Nekrassovski Forcible humanitarian intervention is a military intervention, which interferes coercively in the domestic affairs of another state for the purpose of reducing the suffering of some or all people within that state’s borders. The legality as well as the morality of forcible humanitarian intervention is disputed because the modern international society is built on principles of sovereignty, non-intervention, and the non-use of force (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). In fact, in order to protect state sovereignty, international law traditionally prohibited states from interfering into each other’s internal affairs, especially with military force (Feinstein and Slaughter, 2004). The present paper will assess and counter the arguments against legitimizing the practice of forcible humanitarian intervention. In particular, it will be argued that it is our moral duty to stop a humanitarian crisis in another country; state leaders have every moral right to risk the lives of their military personnel to stop a humanitarian crisis in another country, if this risk and especially the collateral damage caused by the intervention will be outweighed by the total reduction in human suffering that it brings about; if forcible humanitarian intervention is legitimized, subject to such rules and restrictions, there is little need to fear that this right will be abused; the fact that states may only engage in humanitarian interventions in order to promote their national interest, is a misguided objection to legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention. One argument against legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention states that any violation of human rights (for example), within a particular state, is a problem, the responsibility for fixing which falls solely on the shoulders of that state’s citizens and political leaders. Outsiders have no moral duty to intervene even if they can fix it (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). This moral argument does not seem to be particularly convincing, as it suggests that altruism is not a positive moral value. In fact, according to classical utilitarianism, the morally right thing to always do is to seek to bring welfare or happiness to the greatest number of people (Heinze, 2005). Consequently, if there is a humanitarian crisis in a particular state and we can stop it by forcibly intervening, than it is our moral duty to do so. Another argument against legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention, argues that state leaders do not have the moral right to risk the lives of their military personnel merely in order to reduce human suffering (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). Or as Samuel P. Huntington put it, more bluntly, in reference to a specific case of a forcible humanitarian intervention: “it is morally unjustifiable and politically indefensible that members of the [U.S.] armed forces should be killed to prevent Somalis from killing one another” (Smith, 1998). However, Huntington has not usually been known to be a moralist (Smith, 1998), and Smith (1998) himself does not find this argument convincing; nor does the author of the present paper.
  • 2. Interdisciplinary, unpaid research opportunities are available. Various academic specialties are required. If interested, email me at dr.freedom@hotmail.ca. After all, state leaders have the moral right to sacrifice the lives of their military personnel in order to protect their country from foreign threats – a practice which solely benefits the state’s leaders (in terms of greater public support, etc.) and citizens (in terms of greater security), and hence is completely selfish, at least from the point of view of citizens of other nations. On the other hand, societies that allow their leaders to risk the lives of their military personnel in order to reduce human suffering in foreign lands are far more altruistic, and hence morally superior, than those societies that do not allow such a practice. Moreover, military personnel who have joined the armed forces voluntary (as tends to be the case for most armed forces that take part in forcible humanitarian interventions) have consented to any and all risk to their lives that may come from their service in the military. Hence, it is unclear how risking their lives can be immoral. Also, according to utilitarianism, the morally right thing to do is any action that will lead to the greatest total amount of happiness or welfare. Hence, it is permissible to reduce the welfare of some people if these actions will lead to a proportionate, per person increase in welfare of a larger number of other people (Heinze, 2005). Hence, state leaders have every moral right to risk the lives of their military personnel for the sake of a humanitarian intervention, if they are confident that the total human suffering incurred in the process will be outweighed by the total reduction in human suffering that this intervention will bring. But how can states, that may want to intervene, be reasonably sure that they do more good than harm? After all, forcible humanitarian intervention is similar to a military attack; hence it is inevitable that it will harm and even kill some innocent people in the process (Heinze, 2005). Consequently, a humanitarian intervention should only be permissible when there are sufficiently large scale abuses of people that result in sufficiently severe suffering (e. g. large scale massacre, genocide, or ethnic cleansing). While it would not make any humanitarian sense to attempt deposing a regime which engages in “smaller-scale or less severe abuses such as political repression and intimidation” (Heinze, 2005). Also, along the same lines, it is important to note that the state or an international organization, which is considering a specific, forcible humanitarian intervention, must have sufficient military capabilities (and be willing to use them for this intervention) to easily overpower any military opposition that its intervention may encounter in that specific case (Heinze, 2005). If this is not so, and the intervening force is likely to be defeated, than the intervention will only create more suffering for the citizens of the country in a humanitarian crisis and the members of the intervening force. But even if the interveners are likely to win, but the opponent is too strong, intervening would still be unreasonable because a powerful military opposition is likely to lead to great destruction, and hence, more harm than good (Heinze, 2005). All of the above considerations for a morally justifiable intervention are confirmed by the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS), according to which
  • 3. Interdisciplinary, unpaid research opportunities are available. Various academic specialties are required. If interested, email me at dr.freedom@hotmail.ca. forcible humanitarian intervention should only take place when a large-scale loss of life or ethnic cleansing are taking place or are anticipated (Weiss, 2004). Moreover, such an intervention should have ‘right’ intentions, be done only as a last resort, should use proportional means, and have reasonable prospects of success. Finally, for the sake of greater neutrality, the Security Council of the United Nations should be the preferred decision maker in such cases (Weiss, 2004). According to Realists, states only act out of selfish motives. Hence, it is argued that there is a risk that if forcible humanitarian intervention is legitimized, states will start using the right to engage in humanitarian interventions as an excuse and a convenient, noble-sounding cover for engaging in additional selfish pursuits of national interest. In other words, the right to engage in humanitarian interventions is open to abuse (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). However, given the rules, described above, for distinguishing between morally justifiable and unjustifiable humanitarian interventions, only those humanitarian interventions that follow such rules can be legitimized and all the others forbidden, making it hard, if not impossible, to abuse the right to engage in humanitarian intervention. Moreover, there is little reason to believe that all humanitarian interventions that do happen, are done out of selfish motives. Sometimes states engage in forcible humanitarian interventions out of a combination of a desire to appease the humanitarian sentiments of domestic publics and some genuine moral concerns (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). Also, it is argued that because states act only in order to pursue national interest, they engage in humanitarian interventions only, or at least primarily, when they believe that their national interest is at stake. This practice of selecting which humanitarian crises to solve through intervention, based on national interests rather than moral concerns, is deemed as being immoral by its opponents (Bellamy and Wheeler, 2011). Though this practice may indeed be immoral, it is unclear how it can be used as an objection to legitimizing humanitarian intervention. First, because the resources of all states are limited, it would be unrealistic to expect even a hypothetical, morally pure state to attempt to solve all humanitarian crises that arise around the world. Second, even a hypothetical state with unlimited resources, which engages only in those humanitarian interventions which benefit its national interest, still reduces some human suffering in the world. While preventing such a state from engaging in any humanitarian intervention, will mean that it will not be reducing any human suffering at all. Thus, we have seen that intervening into the affairs of another state, in order to solve a humanitarian crisis, is a morally right thing to do. Also, there are several reasons why state leaders have a moral right to risk the lives of their military personnel in order to reduce human suffering in another country. However, forcible humanitarian intervention is only justified when the human suffering, which it will inevitably bring about as a side effect, is smaller than the total amount of human suffering that it will eliminate. This can happen only when the humanitarian crisis is sufficiently severe and when the intervening forces will easily overpower
  • 4. Interdisciplinary, unpaid research opportunities are available. Various academic specialties are required. If interested, email me at dr.freedom@hotmail.ca. all military opposition. Hence, legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention, subject to these and related rules and restrictions, greatly reduces the risk of this right being abused. Finally, there are several reasons why the fact that states may only engage in humanitarian interventions in order to promote their national interest, is a misguided objection to legitimizing forcible humanitarian intervention. References Bellamy, A. and Wheeler, N. (2011). “Humanitarian Intervention in World Politics.” In J. Baylis, S. Smith and P. Owens (Eds.), Globalization of World Politics 5th Edition. New York: Oxford University Press. Feinstein, L. and Slaughter, A.M. (2004). “A Duty to Prevent.” Foreign Affairs. Vol. 83(1), p. 136- 150. Heinz, E. A. (2005). “Commonsense Morality and the Consequentialist Ethics of Humanitarian Intervention.” Journal of Military Ethics. Vol. 4(3), p. 168-182. Smith, M. (1998). “Humanitarian Intervention: An Overview of the Ethical Issues.” Ethics and International Affairs. Vol. 12, p. 63-79. Weiss, T. G. (2004). “The Sunset of Humanitarian Intervention: The Responsibility to Protect in a Unipolar Era.” Security Dialogue. Vol. 35(2), p. 135-153.