SlideShare une entreprise Scribd logo
1  sur  30
Phenomenology,
  Methodology,
   and Theory
David Rosenthal                           Universität Bern
          CUNY Graduate Center                    27 May 2009
          Philosophy and Cognitive
                 Science
http://davidrosenthal1.googlepages.com/
OVERVIEW
   I. First- and Third-Person
       Approaches
   II. Saving the Phenomeno-
       logical Appearances
   III. Phenomenology and
       Theories of Consciousness
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   2
I. First- and Third-Person
           Approaches
Until fewer than 150 years ago,
 theorists routinely tended to regard
     all mental states as conscious.
Even Brentano, who acknowledged that
 “[a]n unconscious consciousness is no
 more a contradiction in terms than an
 unseen case of seeing” (1874/1973, 102),
 nonetheless insisted—
 though without any serious argument—
 that no mental state ever actually
     occurs without being conscious.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   3
The recognition by Brentano and others
 that nonconscious mentality poses no
 conceptual conflict may have led many
 late 19th thinkers, Freud among them,
 to accept that mental states do actually
     occur without being conscious.
And this has pivotal implications for
 theorizing about consciousness.
For one thing, if mental states were all
 conscious, it would be tempting to see
 consciousness as a simple, unanalyzable
 property—as Moore regarded yellow.
That claim has less force if mental states
 aren‟t all conscious, since then we must
     explain how the conscious states differ
     from mental states that aren‟t conscious.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   4
Countenancing mental states that aren‟t
 conscious has another consequence.
Some theorists approach the mind only
 in a first-person way (Nagel, Searle), others
 in just a third-person way (Quine, Dennett?).
But any satisfactory understanding of
 mind must somehow accommodate both.
Not only do we often know about our
 own mental states; we sometimes know
 pretty well about those of others.
Also, when you say of yourself that you‟re
 in pain or that you think that p, you mean
     the very same thing I mean when I say
     those things of you (P. F. Strawson 1958/59).
     The states we ascribe to ourselves are
     the same as those we ascribe to others.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   5
The occurrence of mental states that
 aren‟t conscious reinforces the need to
     accommodate our third-person access.
As Freud recognized (e.g., 1915), if some
 mental states aren‟t conscious, we must
 understand our own nonconscious states
 in the same third-person terms in which
 we understand the states of others.
So there is nothing mysterious about
     mental states that aren‟t conscious:
 We conceive of them just as we conceive
 of the conscious mental states of others.
And their occurrence thereby underscores
 that consciousness and phenomenology
     cannot be our sole source of information
     about mental reality.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   6
A first-person perspective seems to have
 pride of place because it seems to grasp
 mental reality directly—
 and so perhaps more accurately.
But traditional claims of infallibility and
 incorrigibility are dubious. We sometimes
 know better than others what mental
 states they are in—even with qualitative
 states others sometimes stand corrected.
Still, the apparent directness of our first-
 person access to mental states seems
 to make a third-person perspective hard
 to accommodate, since directness would
     make little room—if any at all—for the
     causal ties that are central in a third-
     person understanding of mental states.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   7
On the other hand, a primarily third-
 person approach may seem unable to
 accommodate the apparent directness
 characteristic of our first-person access.
All this leads some to hold that we can‟t
 accommodate both, and we‟re left with
 an unavoidable choice between them.
But that‟s not so.
 Though an exclusively first-person
 approach does not make room for the
 causal ties needed for any third-person
 approach,
     the directness of our first-person access
     is arguably only apparent—
     and so can likely be accommodated by a
     nuanced third-person approach ( III).
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   8
Might one‟s access to others‟ qualitative
 states always rely, possibly indirectly, on
 some first-person avowals?
Arguably not. We might, relying only on
 our third-person sense of when others
 are in pain, train a device that detects
 relevant neural states to determine
 when others are in pain. We could then
 use others‟ first-person reports to confirm
 the device‟s accuracy, but that accuracy
 would rely only on our third-person sense.
And in any case exclusively first-person
 access not susceptible to third-person
 test and correction would arguably be
 idle, since we can have no reason to rely
 on untestable pronouncements.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   9
A higher-order theory can capture all
 this best, by representing the subjective
 directness of our first-person access as
 due to a higher-order awareness of our
 conscious states that is subjectively
     independent of any mediation and also
     independent of any observational input.
This lets us explain how third-person
 access can trump first-person access,
 and how we can have subjectively direct
 access to states that have the rich causal
 ties essential to our third-person access.
I‟ll return in III to these higher-order
 theories. But let‟s turn first to what it is
     for any theory to save the first-person,
     phenomenological appearances.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   10
II. Saving the Phenomeno-
    logical Appearances
It‟s typically assumed—albeit tacitly—
 that doing justice to our first-person,
 phenomenological intuitions means
 regarding those intuitions as true.
Why might that be? Our pretheoretic
 intuitions about other things are often
     incorrect—e.g., about how projectiles
     travel, whether the earth is flat, whether
     subjective color experiences resemble
     the visible properties of objects, and
     whether objects have absolute location.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   11
Even pretheoretic intuitions about
  psychological functioning are often
  wrong—e.g., about whether parafoveal
  vision is rich in detail and color.
Sometimes false pretheoretic intuitions
  are close approximations to the truth;
  sometimes they‟re just wrong.
Perhaps we expect more from first-
  person phenomenological impressions
  because they seem unmediated— and so
  perhaps (relatively) immune from error.
 But again: Such lack of mediation is
     just a phenomenological impression,
     which has little if any independent,
     empirical substantiation—indeed it‟s
     not obvious how it could have any.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   12
Saving the appearances can amount to
 showing that the appearances are true.
But that‟s not what it usually means.
 We save the appearances by showing
 how the way things actually are gives
 rise to those appearances.
So too with our first-person impressions:
     We needn‟t try to do full justice to them
     by showing that they‟re true;
     rather, we can show why it is we have
     those phenomenological impressions—
     how they arise in us.
Indeed, showing our impressions are
 correct can‟t explain why we have those
 impressions; things can be a particular
 way without seeming to be that way.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   13
So saving the phenomenological
 appearances comes down to showing
 why our mental lives appear that way—
     whether or not they really are that way.
The role of phenomenology in building a
 theory of consciousness, then, is to
     provide an accurate catalog of the
     appearances we have of our mental
 lives, as data our theorizing must explain.
And as usual, explaining the data must
     go beyond the data themselves.
     Nor should our theorizing assume at the
     outset that those appearances accurately
     reflect the reality of our mental lives.
     Rather, our theorizing must initially just
     explain why we have those appearances.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   14
 Phenomenology is mental appearance:
  It is the way qualitative mental states
  appear to us—how we‟re aware of them.
  So for phenomenology, appearance
 coincides with reality.
They might also coincide for the mental
 itself if mental states were all conscious.
 But since many mental states fail to be
 conscious, mental appearance does not
 exhaust the reality of the mental.
The phenomenological appearances
 reveal only how we are conscious, in a
 first-person way, of mental reality.
 To investigate that mental reality itself,
     we must go beyond phenomenology—
     beyond the first-person appearances.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   15
We can best do that by relying on folk-
 psychological platitudes (Lewis 1966/71, 1972,
 1999)—which are cast in third- as well as
     first-person terms.
Phenomenological appearances are real.
 And our explanation of mental reality
 must explain why it appears as it does.
But it must explain more than just that.
 So we have a fruitful division of labor:
 We can explain some features of
 conscious states just as we explain their
 nonconscious mental counterparts.
 And we can also seek to isolate that
 additional factor which results in some
 mental states‟ being conscious.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   16
These observations have implications for
 theories of consciousness.
 I suggested that higher-order theories
 have the best shot at doing justice both
 to the first-person appearances that our
 conscious states present us with
 and to the rich causal properties that
 we know all our mental states have.
Is our higher-order awareness external
 to the states that are conscious?
 Or might it be intrinsic to those states?
It might seem that intrinsicalism better
 saves the phenomenological appearances,
 since our awareness of our conscious
     states appears to be intrinsic to those
     states (Gennaro 1996, 2008; Natsoulas?).
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   17
But as with the appearance of directness,
 we must explain why we have this
 appearance, but needn‟t see it as true.
And we can best explain that simply by
 seeing our awareness of our conscious
 states as typically due to a distinct state
     of which we aren‟t, in turn aware.
Kriegel (2006) urges that we‟re always
 aware—albeit usually peripherally—of our
 higher-order awareness. But that‟s not
 so: Consider conscious visual perceiving
 that is relatively peripheral.
 And there are compelling independent
 reasons to deny that the higher-order
 awareness is intrinsic either to intentional
 or to qualitative conscious states.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   18
III. Phenomenology and
  Theories of Consciousness
These methodological points to one side,
     some may doubt that any theory not
     itself based on phenomenology can do
     justice to the first-person appearances.
In closing, I‟ll mention a few challenges
 of this sort and briefly sketch how a
 higher-order theory can deal with them.
I‟ll sometimes appeal to my own higher-
 order-thought (HOT) theory,
 but many points (though not quite all) will
 hold for any higher-order theory.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   19
Can a higher-order theory save the idea
 that our first-person access is
     epistemically privileged?
No. But we have only the appearance
 of privilege—and we can‟t export from
 an apparent privilege to an actual
 privilege for the appearances.
Also, we can capture that appearance
 in third-person terms. Suppose that a
 state is conscious if one is aware of it by
 having a HOT that one is in that state.
That awareness will seem direct if it relies
     on no observation and on no conscious
     inference. And any such awareness will
     also appear to be privileged— relative to
     our ordinary observational access.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   20
Such privilege aside, how can any third-
 person theory capture the way conscious
 qualitative states are “lighted up”—in
 contrast to nonconscious mental states?
There is reason to think that HOTs do
     result in conscious qualitative character:
     We sometimes learn to taste wines or
     distinguish musical sounds by having
     words to classify distinct experiences.
     Having „tannin‟ and „acid‟ (or „clarinet‟ or
     „oboe‟) available to label mental qualities
     can, by itself, lead to mental qualities
     that are subjectively more fine grained.
 Having words to pin the experiences on
     actually affects what it‟s like for one to
     have those experiences.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   21
 How can learning words have that effect?
  It‟s not credible that learning new words
  actually causes new mental qualities; no
  known mechanism could explain that.
But words express thoughts. And since
  the words here describe one‟s own
  mental qualities, the thoughts expressed
     are HOTs.
     Learning new words leads to becoming
     conscious of our mental qualities in more
     fine-grained ways; so the new subjective
 appearances must be due to new HOTs.
The content of our HOTs does affect how
 our qualitative states are conscious.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   22
This explanation may not resolve the
 explanatory gap (Levine 2001) that some
 see as separating conscious qualitative
 character from everything else.
But proponents of the explanatory gap
 insist on an explanation that will seem
 rational independent of suitable theory.
 And an explanation can do that only if it
     explains the phenomenological data by
     appeal to the phenomenological itself—
 within that closed circle of appearances.
Such an explanation will be uninformative:
 We can never informatively explain a
 phenomenon in terms of itself;
 we must in some way go beyond the
     phenomenon we seek to explain.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   23
Nagel meant his famous (1974) rubric,
 „what it‟s like for one‟, to capture not just
 the lighted-up character of conscious
 mental qualities,
 but also their subjectivity.
But we needn‟t adopt Nagel‟s question-
 begging construal of subjectivity as
 excluding the objective (Rosenthal 1983).
Rather, we should see the subjective as
     being a special case of the objective:
     It is that aspect of mentality that
     depends to a large extent on individual
     perspective—location, history, and other
     features of an individual‟s points of view—
     and on features of one‟s perceptual
     apparatus that affect mental qualities.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   24
We can understand all these subjective
 features of an individual‟s mental life in
     fully objective terms—
 indeed, in terms of the ways HOTs result
 in one‟s being aware oneself as being in
 states with various mental properties.
Conflating mental appearance with
 mental reality adversely affects
 theorizing.
 If, e.g., mental reality were just its first-
 person appearance, then you couldn‟t
 know whether your conscious sensation
 of red is the same as mine, or even if I
 have any conscious sensations at all.
But there‟s more to mental reality than
 its first-person mental appearance.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   25
So we can understand the mental
 qualities not just in first-person terms,
 but also in terms of their role in
 perceiving— by reference to location in
 a quality space that corresponds to that
 of the relevant perceptible properties.
That lets us explain why the actual
  quality spaces are asymmetric in ways
  that preclude such fanciful inter-personal
  quality inversion.
 Such inversion seems conceivable only if
  we restrict ourselves to the first-person
  appearances our sensations present.
     And since HOTs describe states in terms
     of their mental properties, inversion also
     won‟t affect the first-person appearances.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   26
What about our sense of the unity of
     consciousness?
Again, phenomenology, by itself, delivers
 only the appearance of unity.
 And the HOT model has the resources to
 explain these appearances:
 Each HOT represents its target as
 belonging to a self—and absent some
     reason to distinguish among the selves
     to which the various HOTs refer (as
     happens with dissociative identity disorder),
     a subjective impression of unity results.
It‟s altogether another question whether
 there is some underlying mental unity in
     addition to the subjective unity of the
     phenomenological appearances.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   27
We also have a subjective impression of
 freedom— that our volitions are free and
 uncaused. That sense of freedom reflects
                                 he




     our seldom being aware of our volitions
     as being caused by anything prior.
  We can explain that in turn as due to
  HOTs‟ not representing their targets in
  respect of any such causal ties.
Indeed, we seldom have any phenom-
  enological impression of mental states‟
  having any causal ties—which is arguably
  due to how HOTs represent those states.
 That doesn‟t mean that our volitions are
  uncaused— just as there may be no real
  mental unity. But we do have a robust
     subjective impression of those things.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   28
Summary
Phenomenology provides some of the
 data that a theory of mind must explain:
 data about the first-person appearances
 of the underlying mental reality.
Since mental states can occur without
 being conscious, appearance and reality
     cannot coincide for the mental itself—
 as they do for phenomenology.
Phenomenology reveals only how we are
 conscious, in a first-person way, of the
 mental. To investigate mental reality
 itself we must go beyond phenomenology.
Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   29
THANK YOU FOR
            YOUR ATTENTION



Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory   Universität Bern, 27 May 2009   30

Contenu connexe

Tendances

Phenomenological Research
Phenomenological Research Phenomenological Research
Phenomenological Research A. Q.
 
Husserl's phenomenology a short introduction for psychologists
Husserl's phenomenology a short introduction for psychologistsHusserl's phenomenology a short introduction for psychologists
Husserl's phenomenology a short introduction for psychologistsMarc Applebaum, PhD
 
Phenomenology of husserl
Phenomenology of husserlPhenomenology of husserl
Phenomenology of husserlJerick Serandon
 
Phenomenology research methodology
Phenomenology research methodologyPhenomenology research methodology
Phenomenology research methodologyFernando Santos
 
Empiricism and Rationalism
Empiricism and RationalismEmpiricism and Rationalism
Empiricism and RationalismCDAGCUF
 
Phenomenological Research
Phenomenological ResearchPhenomenological Research
Phenomenological ResearchSue Quirante
 
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and EmpicismClassic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and EmpicismMusfera Nara Vadia
 
Ethnography research 1
Ethnography  research 1Ethnography  research 1
Ethnography research 1Joshua Batalla
 
Ppt Psychoanalytic Theory Sigmund Freud
Ppt Psychoanalytic Theory Sigmund FreudPpt Psychoanalytic Theory Sigmund Freud
Ppt Psychoanalytic Theory Sigmund FreudKamarina Tajuddin
 
philosophy of science, Falsification theory, Karl popper
philosophy of science, Falsification theory, Karl popperphilosophy of science, Falsification theory, Karl popper
philosophy of science, Falsification theory, Karl popperKhalid Zaffar
 

Tendances (20)

Phenomenological Research
Phenomenological Research Phenomenological Research
Phenomenological Research
 
Phenomenology
PhenomenologyPhenomenology
Phenomenology
 
Phenomenology
PhenomenologyPhenomenology
Phenomenology
 
Husserl's phenomenology a short introduction for psychologists
Husserl's phenomenology a short introduction for psychologistsHusserl's phenomenology a short introduction for psychologists
Husserl's phenomenology a short introduction for psychologists
 
Phenomenology of husserl
Phenomenology of husserlPhenomenology of husserl
Phenomenology of husserl
 
Phenomenology research methodology
Phenomenology research methodologyPhenomenology research methodology
Phenomenology research methodology
 
Psychoanalysis ppt
Psychoanalysis pptPsychoanalysis ppt
Psychoanalysis ppt
 
PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH
PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCHPHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH
PHENOMENOLOGICAL RESEARCH
 
Phenomenology
PhenomenologyPhenomenology
Phenomenology
 
Ethnography Research
Ethnography ResearchEthnography Research
Ethnography Research
 
Empiricism and Rationalism
Empiricism and RationalismEmpiricism and Rationalism
Empiricism and Rationalism
 
Part #1
Part #1Part #1
Part #1
 
phenomenological
phenomenologicalphenomenological
phenomenological
 
Phenomenological Research
Phenomenological ResearchPhenomenological Research
Phenomenological Research
 
Epistemology
EpistemologyEpistemology
Epistemology
 
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and EmpicismClassic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
Classic and Modern Philosophy: Rationalism and Empicism
 
Ethnography research 1
Ethnography  research 1Ethnography  research 1
Ethnography research 1
 
Ppt Psychoanalytic Theory Sigmund Freud
Ppt Psychoanalytic Theory Sigmund FreudPpt Psychoanalytic Theory Sigmund Freud
Ppt Psychoanalytic Theory Sigmund Freud
 
philosophy of science, Falsification theory, Karl popper
philosophy of science, Falsification theory, Karl popperphilosophy of science, Falsification theory, Karl popper
philosophy of science, Falsification theory, Karl popper
 
Phenomonology
PhenomonologyPhenomonology
Phenomonology
 

Similaire à "Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory"

Consciousness Society: Validation of First and Second Person Methods for Inqu...
Consciousness Society: Validation of First and Second Person Methods for Inqu...Consciousness Society: Validation of First and Second Person Methods for Inqu...
Consciousness Society: Validation of First and Second Person Methods for Inqu...Robert Wright, Jr.
 
Epistemology and the problem of knowledge
Epistemology and the problem of knowledgeEpistemology and the problem of knowledge
Epistemology and the problem of knowledgeNoel Jopson
 
Historicalroots1.ppt
Historicalroots1.pptHistoricalroots1.ppt
Historicalroots1.pptJumaGull
 
History of Psychology: Historical roots 1
History of Psychology: Historical roots 1History of Psychology: Historical roots 1
History of Psychology: Historical roots 1Catina Feresin
 
Applebaum: Themes in phenomenological psychological research
Applebaum: Themes in phenomenological psychological researchApplebaum: Themes in phenomenological psychological research
Applebaum: Themes in phenomenological psychological researchMarc Applebaum, PhD
 
Introspection Vs Behaviorism
Introspection Vs BehaviorismIntrospection Vs Behaviorism
Introspection Vs BehaviorismLanate Drummond
 
Sigmund Freud on 'The Psychic Apparatus'
Sigmund Freud on 'The Psychic Apparatus'Sigmund Freud on 'The Psychic Apparatus'
Sigmund Freud on 'The Psychic Apparatus'Shiva Kumar Srinivasan
 

Similaire à "Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory" (13)

Consciousness Society: Validation of First and Second Person Methods for Inqu...
Consciousness Society: Validation of First and Second Person Methods for Inqu...Consciousness Society: Validation of First and Second Person Methods for Inqu...
Consciousness Society: Validation of First and Second Person Methods for Inqu...
 
Essay On Perception
Essay On PerceptionEssay On Perception
Essay On Perception
 
Chapter 3
Chapter 3Chapter 3
Chapter 3
 
Epistemology and the problem of knowledge
Epistemology and the problem of knowledgeEpistemology and the problem of knowledge
Epistemology and the problem of knowledge
 
Historicalroots1.ppt
Historicalroots1.pptHistoricalroots1.ppt
Historicalroots1.ppt
 
History of Psychology: Historical roots 1
History of Psychology: Historical roots 1History of Psychology: Historical roots 1
History of Psychology: Historical roots 1
 
Applebaum: Themes in phenomenological psychological research
Applebaum: Themes in phenomenological psychological researchApplebaum: Themes in phenomenological psychological research
Applebaum: Themes in phenomenological psychological research
 
Rosenthal m qs-wo-cn
Rosenthal m qs-wo-cnRosenthal m qs-wo-cn
Rosenthal m qs-wo-cn
 
Introspection Vs Behaviorism
Introspection Vs BehaviorismIntrospection Vs Behaviorism
Introspection Vs Behaviorism
 
Thought and Reason
Thought and ReasonThought and Reason
Thought and Reason
 
Sigmund Freud on 'The Psychic Apparatus'
Sigmund Freud on 'The Psychic Apparatus'Sigmund Freud on 'The Psychic Apparatus'
Sigmund Freud on 'The Psychic Apparatus'
 
Vaidya_JCS_Author_Proof[1]
Vaidya_JCS_Author_Proof[1]Vaidya_JCS_Author_Proof[1]
Vaidya_JCS_Author_Proof[1]
 
Emotions v2
Emotions v2Emotions v2
Emotions v2
 

Plus de David Rosenthal

Thought, Speech, and Conscious
Thought, Speech, and ConsciousThought, Speech, and Conscious
Thought, Speech, and ConsciousDavid Rosenthal
 
Relocation, Quality Spaces, and Grain
Relocation, Quality Spaces, and GrainRelocation, Quality Spaces, and Grain
Relocation, Quality Spaces, and GrainDavid Rosenthal
 
"Mental Qualities, Valence, and Intuition"
"Mental Qualities, Valence, and Intuition""Mental Qualities, Valence, and Intuition"
"Mental Qualities, Valence, and Intuition"David Rosenthal
 
"Translation and Understanding"
"Translation and Understanding""Translation and Understanding"
"Translation and Understanding"David Rosenthal
 
"Conscious Awareness, Higher-Order Theories, and Overflow"
"Conscious Awareness, Higher-Order Theories, and Overflow""Conscious Awareness, Higher-Order Theories, and Overflow"
"Conscious Awareness, Higher-Order Theories, and Overflow"David Rosenthal
 

Plus de David Rosenthal (6)

Dr kent-sellars
Dr kent-sellarsDr kent-sellars
Dr kent-sellars
 
Thought, Speech, and Conscious
Thought, Speech, and ConsciousThought, Speech, and Conscious
Thought, Speech, and Conscious
 
Relocation, Quality Spaces, and Grain
Relocation, Quality Spaces, and GrainRelocation, Quality Spaces, and Grain
Relocation, Quality Spaces, and Grain
 
"Mental Qualities, Valence, and Intuition"
"Mental Qualities, Valence, and Intuition""Mental Qualities, Valence, and Intuition"
"Mental Qualities, Valence, and Intuition"
 
"Translation and Understanding"
"Translation and Understanding""Translation and Understanding"
"Translation and Understanding"
 
"Conscious Awareness, Higher-Order Theories, and Overflow"
"Conscious Awareness, Higher-Order Theories, and Overflow""Conscious Awareness, Higher-Order Theories, and Overflow"
"Conscious Awareness, Higher-Order Theories, and Overflow"
 

Dernier

Privatization and Disinvestment - Meaning, Objectives, Advantages and Disadva...
Privatization and Disinvestment - Meaning, Objectives, Advantages and Disadva...Privatization and Disinvestment - Meaning, Objectives, Advantages and Disadva...
Privatization and Disinvestment - Meaning, Objectives, Advantages and Disadva...RKavithamani
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13Steve Thomason
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...Marc Dusseiller Dusjagr
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxNirmalaLoungPoorunde1
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxiammrhaywood
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdfssuser54595a
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpin
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpinStudent login on Anyboli platform.helpin
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpinRaunakKeshri1
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeThiyagu K
 
Industrial Policy - 1948, 1956, 1973, 1977, 1980, 1991
Industrial Policy - 1948, 1956, 1973, 1977, 1980, 1991Industrial Policy - 1948, 1956, 1973, 1977, 1980, 1991
Industrial Policy - 1948, 1956, 1973, 1977, 1980, 1991RKavithamani
 
Grant Readiness 101 TechSoup and Remy Consulting
Grant Readiness 101 TechSoup and Remy ConsultingGrant Readiness 101 TechSoup and Remy Consulting
Grant Readiness 101 TechSoup and Remy ConsultingTechSoup
 
Web & Social Media Analytics Previous Year Question Paper.pdf
Web & Social Media Analytics Previous Year Question Paper.pdfWeb & Social Media Analytics Previous Year Question Paper.pdf
Web & Social Media Analytics Previous Year Question Paper.pdfJayanti Pande
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfSoniaTolstoy
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Krashi Coaching
 
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactAccessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactdawncurless
 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdfQucHHunhnh
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Sapana Sha
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxmanuelaromero2013
 

Dernier (20)

Privatization and Disinvestment - Meaning, Objectives, Advantages and Disadva...
Privatization and Disinvestment - Meaning, Objectives, Advantages and Disadva...Privatization and Disinvestment - Meaning, Objectives, Advantages and Disadva...
Privatization and Disinvestment - Meaning, Objectives, Advantages and Disadva...
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
 
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
“Oh GOSH! Reflecting on Hackteria's Collaborative Practices in a Global Do-It...
 
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptxEmployee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
Employee wellbeing at the workplace.pptx
 
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptxSOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
SOCIAL AND HISTORICAL CONTEXT - LFTVD.pptx
 
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
18-04-UA_REPORT_MEDIALITERAСY_INDEX-DM_23-1-final-eng.pdf
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpin
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpinStudent login on Anyboli platform.helpin
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpin
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
 
Industrial Policy - 1948, 1956, 1973, 1977, 1980, 1991
Industrial Policy - 1948, 1956, 1973, 1977, 1980, 1991Industrial Policy - 1948, 1956, 1973, 1977, 1980, 1991
Industrial Policy - 1948, 1956, 1973, 1977, 1980, 1991
 
Grant Readiness 101 TechSoup and Remy Consulting
Grant Readiness 101 TechSoup and Remy ConsultingGrant Readiness 101 TechSoup and Remy Consulting
Grant Readiness 101 TechSoup and Remy Consulting
 
Web & Social Media Analytics Previous Year Question Paper.pdf
Web & Social Media Analytics Previous Year Question Paper.pdfWeb & Social Media Analytics Previous Year Question Paper.pdf
Web & Social Media Analytics Previous Year Question Paper.pdf
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
 
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactAccessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
 
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf1029 -  Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
1029 - Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa 10 . pdf
 
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
Call Girls in Dwarka Mor Delhi Contact Us 9654467111
 
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdfTataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
TataKelola dan KamSiber Kecerdasan Buatan v022.pdf
 
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSDStaff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
Staff of Color (SOC) Retention Efforts DDSD
 
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptxHow to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
How to Make a Pirate ship Primary Education.pptx
 

"Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory"

  • 1. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory David Rosenthal Universität Bern CUNY Graduate Center 27 May 2009 Philosophy and Cognitive Science http://davidrosenthal1.googlepages.com/
  • 2. OVERVIEW  I. First- and Third-Person Approaches  II. Saving the Phenomeno- logical Appearances  III. Phenomenology and Theories of Consciousness Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 2
  • 3. I. First- and Third-Person Approaches Until fewer than 150 years ago, theorists routinely tended to regard all mental states as conscious. Even Brentano, who acknowledged that “[a]n unconscious consciousness is no more a contradiction in terms than an unseen case of seeing” (1874/1973, 102), nonetheless insisted— though without any serious argument— that no mental state ever actually occurs without being conscious. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 3
  • 4. The recognition by Brentano and others that nonconscious mentality poses no conceptual conflict may have led many late 19th thinkers, Freud among them, to accept that mental states do actually occur without being conscious. And this has pivotal implications for theorizing about consciousness. For one thing, if mental states were all conscious, it would be tempting to see consciousness as a simple, unanalyzable property—as Moore regarded yellow. That claim has less force if mental states aren‟t all conscious, since then we must explain how the conscious states differ from mental states that aren‟t conscious. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 4
  • 5. Countenancing mental states that aren‟t conscious has another consequence. Some theorists approach the mind only in a first-person way (Nagel, Searle), others in just a third-person way (Quine, Dennett?). But any satisfactory understanding of mind must somehow accommodate both. Not only do we often know about our own mental states; we sometimes know pretty well about those of others. Also, when you say of yourself that you‟re in pain or that you think that p, you mean the very same thing I mean when I say those things of you (P. F. Strawson 1958/59). The states we ascribe to ourselves are the same as those we ascribe to others. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 5
  • 6. The occurrence of mental states that aren‟t conscious reinforces the need to accommodate our third-person access. As Freud recognized (e.g., 1915), if some mental states aren‟t conscious, we must understand our own nonconscious states in the same third-person terms in which we understand the states of others. So there is nothing mysterious about mental states that aren‟t conscious: We conceive of them just as we conceive of the conscious mental states of others. And their occurrence thereby underscores that consciousness and phenomenology cannot be our sole source of information about mental reality. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 6
  • 7. A first-person perspective seems to have pride of place because it seems to grasp mental reality directly— and so perhaps more accurately. But traditional claims of infallibility and incorrigibility are dubious. We sometimes know better than others what mental states they are in—even with qualitative states others sometimes stand corrected. Still, the apparent directness of our first- person access to mental states seems to make a third-person perspective hard to accommodate, since directness would make little room—if any at all—for the causal ties that are central in a third- person understanding of mental states. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 7
  • 8. On the other hand, a primarily third- person approach may seem unable to accommodate the apparent directness characteristic of our first-person access. All this leads some to hold that we can‟t accommodate both, and we‟re left with an unavoidable choice between them. But that‟s not so. Though an exclusively first-person approach does not make room for the causal ties needed for any third-person approach, the directness of our first-person access is arguably only apparent— and so can likely be accommodated by a nuanced third-person approach ( III). Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 8
  • 9. Might one‟s access to others‟ qualitative states always rely, possibly indirectly, on some first-person avowals? Arguably not. We might, relying only on our third-person sense of when others are in pain, train a device that detects relevant neural states to determine when others are in pain. We could then use others‟ first-person reports to confirm the device‟s accuracy, but that accuracy would rely only on our third-person sense. And in any case exclusively first-person access not susceptible to third-person test and correction would arguably be idle, since we can have no reason to rely on untestable pronouncements. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 9
  • 10. A higher-order theory can capture all this best, by representing the subjective directness of our first-person access as due to a higher-order awareness of our conscious states that is subjectively independent of any mediation and also independent of any observational input. This lets us explain how third-person access can trump first-person access, and how we can have subjectively direct access to states that have the rich causal ties essential to our third-person access. I‟ll return in III to these higher-order theories. But let‟s turn first to what it is for any theory to save the first-person, phenomenological appearances. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 10
  • 11. II. Saving the Phenomeno- logical Appearances It‟s typically assumed—albeit tacitly— that doing justice to our first-person, phenomenological intuitions means regarding those intuitions as true. Why might that be? Our pretheoretic intuitions about other things are often incorrect—e.g., about how projectiles travel, whether the earth is flat, whether subjective color experiences resemble the visible properties of objects, and whether objects have absolute location. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 11
  • 12. Even pretheoretic intuitions about psychological functioning are often wrong—e.g., about whether parafoveal vision is rich in detail and color. Sometimes false pretheoretic intuitions are close approximations to the truth; sometimes they‟re just wrong. Perhaps we expect more from first- person phenomenological impressions because they seem unmediated— and so perhaps (relatively) immune from error.  But again: Such lack of mediation is just a phenomenological impression, which has little if any independent, empirical substantiation—indeed it‟s not obvious how it could have any. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 12
  • 13. Saving the appearances can amount to showing that the appearances are true. But that‟s not what it usually means. We save the appearances by showing how the way things actually are gives rise to those appearances. So too with our first-person impressions: We needn‟t try to do full justice to them by showing that they‟re true; rather, we can show why it is we have those phenomenological impressions— how they arise in us. Indeed, showing our impressions are correct can‟t explain why we have those impressions; things can be a particular way without seeming to be that way. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 13
  • 14. So saving the phenomenological appearances comes down to showing why our mental lives appear that way— whether or not they really are that way. The role of phenomenology in building a theory of consciousness, then, is to provide an accurate catalog of the appearances we have of our mental lives, as data our theorizing must explain. And as usual, explaining the data must go beyond the data themselves. Nor should our theorizing assume at the outset that those appearances accurately reflect the reality of our mental lives. Rather, our theorizing must initially just explain why we have those appearances. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 14
  • 15.  Phenomenology is mental appearance: It is the way qualitative mental states appear to us—how we‟re aware of them. So for phenomenology, appearance coincides with reality. They might also coincide for the mental itself if mental states were all conscious. But since many mental states fail to be conscious, mental appearance does not exhaust the reality of the mental. The phenomenological appearances reveal only how we are conscious, in a first-person way, of mental reality. To investigate that mental reality itself, we must go beyond phenomenology— beyond the first-person appearances. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 15
  • 16. We can best do that by relying on folk- psychological platitudes (Lewis 1966/71, 1972, 1999)—which are cast in third- as well as first-person terms. Phenomenological appearances are real. And our explanation of mental reality must explain why it appears as it does. But it must explain more than just that. So we have a fruitful division of labor: We can explain some features of conscious states just as we explain their nonconscious mental counterparts. And we can also seek to isolate that additional factor which results in some mental states‟ being conscious. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 16
  • 17. These observations have implications for theories of consciousness. I suggested that higher-order theories have the best shot at doing justice both to the first-person appearances that our conscious states present us with and to the rich causal properties that we know all our mental states have. Is our higher-order awareness external to the states that are conscious? Or might it be intrinsic to those states? It might seem that intrinsicalism better saves the phenomenological appearances, since our awareness of our conscious states appears to be intrinsic to those states (Gennaro 1996, 2008; Natsoulas?). Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 17
  • 18. But as with the appearance of directness, we must explain why we have this appearance, but needn‟t see it as true. And we can best explain that simply by seeing our awareness of our conscious states as typically due to a distinct state of which we aren‟t, in turn aware. Kriegel (2006) urges that we‟re always aware—albeit usually peripherally—of our higher-order awareness. But that‟s not so: Consider conscious visual perceiving that is relatively peripheral. And there are compelling independent reasons to deny that the higher-order awareness is intrinsic either to intentional or to qualitative conscious states. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 18
  • 19. III. Phenomenology and Theories of Consciousness These methodological points to one side, some may doubt that any theory not itself based on phenomenology can do justice to the first-person appearances. In closing, I‟ll mention a few challenges of this sort and briefly sketch how a higher-order theory can deal with them. I‟ll sometimes appeal to my own higher- order-thought (HOT) theory, but many points (though not quite all) will hold for any higher-order theory. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 19
  • 20. Can a higher-order theory save the idea that our first-person access is epistemically privileged? No. But we have only the appearance of privilege—and we can‟t export from an apparent privilege to an actual privilege for the appearances. Also, we can capture that appearance in third-person terms. Suppose that a state is conscious if one is aware of it by having a HOT that one is in that state. That awareness will seem direct if it relies on no observation and on no conscious inference. And any such awareness will also appear to be privileged— relative to our ordinary observational access. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 20
  • 21. Such privilege aside, how can any third- person theory capture the way conscious qualitative states are “lighted up”—in contrast to nonconscious mental states? There is reason to think that HOTs do result in conscious qualitative character: We sometimes learn to taste wines or distinguish musical sounds by having words to classify distinct experiences. Having „tannin‟ and „acid‟ (or „clarinet‟ or „oboe‟) available to label mental qualities can, by itself, lead to mental qualities that are subjectively more fine grained.  Having words to pin the experiences on actually affects what it‟s like for one to have those experiences. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 21
  • 22.  How can learning words have that effect? It‟s not credible that learning new words actually causes new mental qualities; no known mechanism could explain that. But words express thoughts. And since the words here describe one‟s own mental qualities, the thoughts expressed are HOTs. Learning new words leads to becoming conscious of our mental qualities in more fine-grained ways; so the new subjective appearances must be due to new HOTs. The content of our HOTs does affect how our qualitative states are conscious. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 22
  • 23. This explanation may not resolve the explanatory gap (Levine 2001) that some see as separating conscious qualitative character from everything else. But proponents of the explanatory gap insist on an explanation that will seem rational independent of suitable theory. And an explanation can do that only if it explains the phenomenological data by appeal to the phenomenological itself— within that closed circle of appearances. Such an explanation will be uninformative: We can never informatively explain a phenomenon in terms of itself; we must in some way go beyond the phenomenon we seek to explain. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 23
  • 24. Nagel meant his famous (1974) rubric, „what it‟s like for one‟, to capture not just the lighted-up character of conscious mental qualities, but also their subjectivity. But we needn‟t adopt Nagel‟s question- begging construal of subjectivity as excluding the objective (Rosenthal 1983). Rather, we should see the subjective as being a special case of the objective: It is that aspect of mentality that depends to a large extent on individual perspective—location, history, and other features of an individual‟s points of view— and on features of one‟s perceptual apparatus that affect mental qualities. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 24
  • 25. We can understand all these subjective features of an individual‟s mental life in fully objective terms— indeed, in terms of the ways HOTs result in one‟s being aware oneself as being in states with various mental properties. Conflating mental appearance with mental reality adversely affects theorizing. If, e.g., mental reality were just its first- person appearance, then you couldn‟t know whether your conscious sensation of red is the same as mine, or even if I have any conscious sensations at all. But there‟s more to mental reality than its first-person mental appearance. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 25
  • 26. So we can understand the mental qualities not just in first-person terms, but also in terms of their role in perceiving— by reference to location in a quality space that corresponds to that of the relevant perceptible properties. That lets us explain why the actual quality spaces are asymmetric in ways that preclude such fanciful inter-personal quality inversion.  Such inversion seems conceivable only if we restrict ourselves to the first-person appearances our sensations present. And since HOTs describe states in terms of their mental properties, inversion also won‟t affect the first-person appearances. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 26
  • 27. What about our sense of the unity of consciousness? Again, phenomenology, by itself, delivers only the appearance of unity. And the HOT model has the resources to explain these appearances: Each HOT represents its target as belonging to a self—and absent some reason to distinguish among the selves to which the various HOTs refer (as happens with dissociative identity disorder), a subjective impression of unity results. It‟s altogether another question whether there is some underlying mental unity in addition to the subjective unity of the phenomenological appearances. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 27
  • 28. We also have a subjective impression of freedom— that our volitions are free and uncaused. That sense of freedom reflects he our seldom being aware of our volitions as being caused by anything prior. We can explain that in turn as due to HOTs‟ not representing their targets in respect of any such causal ties. Indeed, we seldom have any phenom- enological impression of mental states‟ having any causal ties—which is arguably due to how HOTs represent those states.  That doesn‟t mean that our volitions are uncaused— just as there may be no real mental unity. But we do have a robust subjective impression of those things. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 28
  • 29. Summary Phenomenology provides some of the data that a theory of mind must explain: data about the first-person appearances of the underlying mental reality. Since mental states can occur without being conscious, appearance and reality cannot coincide for the mental itself— as they do for phenomenology. Phenomenology reveals only how we are conscious, in a first-person way, of the mental. To investigate mental reality itself we must go beyond phenomenology. Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 29
  • 30. THANK YOU FOR YOUR ATTENTION Phenomenology, Methodology, and Theory Universität Bern, 27 May 2009 30