SlideShare a Scribd company logo
1 of 23
On The Imaginary Power of Liberation – an Existential Phenomenological Analysis 
Implicit in the writings of Jean-Paul Sartre on the imaginary is a conviction that any 
psychology must apprehend the human ‘in situation’,1 its methodology grounded in a general 
principle of inquiry that has an overt practicality, rather than in a conception of human reality 
that has been, as Sartre claims, ‘described and fixed by an intuition a priori’.2 Such a 
conviction underlies this phenomenological analysis3 of the Sartrean thesis that ‘every 
concrete and real situation of consciousness in the world is pregnant with the imaginary in so 
far as it is always presented as a surpassing of the real’;4 my purpose being to reveal, from the 
way the imaginary is thus shown to function in consciousness, a paradox at the heart of this 
1 
thesis. 
The essay has the following structure: 1. Methodology: Eidetic Reflection, a method that 
clarifies that which is essential about a phenomenon of the imaginary. 2. Making Sense of 
the Imaginary, the imaginary is given its fullest sense, so that, 3. Reflecting on the 
Imaginary, it can be reflected upon to determine its essence. It is not perception, and, 4. 
Knowing the Imaginary, it is informed by knowledge, but the latter makes no advancement. 
Therefore, 5. Living Through the Imaginary, the imaginary cannot exemplify reality, but is 
motivated by the latter, but then, 6. The Paradox of the Imaginary, the imaginary is self-creating 
if it is to be motivated by real situations that are a product of itself. However, 7. 
Conclusion: The Treachery of Images, this paradox emerges because Sartre characterizes 
the imaginary through a referral to the real, the latter taken as obvious. 
1 Jean- Paul Sartre, The Imaginary, (London: Routledge, 2004), p. 186. 
2 Jean-Paul Sartre, Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions, (London: Methuen & Co. Ltd, 1962), p. 93. 
3 Phenomenology follows Descartes on how to avoid error: ‘Whatever method of proof I use, I am always 
brought back to the fact that it is only what I clearly and distinctly perceive that completely convinces me’. 
(René Descartes, ‘Meditations’, in Philosophical Writings, Vol. II, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 
1984). p.47). That is, neither obscure nor confused, or whatever is immediately given to me, the phenomena; I 
confine myself to describing these. 
4 Ibid. 1, p. 186.
2 
1. Methodology: Eidetic Reflection 
Eidetic reflection is a descriptive method whereby, as Sartre says, we ‘produc[e] images in 
ourselves, reflect on these images, describe them, which is to say, try to determine and 
classify their distinctive characteristics’.5 The objective is an imaginary that is indicative of a 
human reality that is situated, but is something more than merely a description of various 
givens; the latter being the procedure of traditional psychologies.6 Perhaps such a procedure 
threatens a naïve Cartesianism, whereby it is supposed that through the performance of some 
reflective act the phenomenologist can simply describe the object of reflection, despite the 
very act of description bringing with it the possibility of misdescription. But eidetic 
reflection begins with a psychological fact, the image, and through a process of imaginatively 
varying its different aspects, the limitations in this variation are thereby given immediately 
and with certainty; I then intuit the eidos, or essence, that which cannot be varied, even in 
imagination, of the object. It investigates the phenomenon through an explication of its 
essence, and has at least the form of a conceptual analysis, the specifying of the necessary 
conditions for the correct application of a concept. 
It may be objected that appropriating the human ‘in situation’ already presupposes a 
conception of human reality. But this is simply a regulative idea required by the method. As 
Sartre explains, ‘the various disciplines of phenomenological psychology are regressive, 
although the ultimate term of their regression is, for them, purely ideal’.7 Although my 
method will restrict itself to the phenomenon on which I reflect, I will not attain immediate 
access to it, though I will be guided by a regulative ideal of human reality, with the proviso 
5 Ibid. 1, p. 5. 
6 For example, psychoanalysis, whereby the image is a ‘material trace, an inanimate element that afterwards 
plays the role of symbol’. (Ibid. 1, p. 97). As Jeanson says, with these views ‘there is a power in consciousness, 
but it is not a power of consciousness’. (Francis Jeanson, Sartre and the Problem of Morality (Indiana: Indiana 
University Press, 1980), p. 25). 
7 Ibid. 2, pp. 93 – 94.
that, just as Sartre found with his study of the emotions that phenomenology is unable to 
‘show that human-reality must necessarily manifest itself in such emotions as it does’, and 
‘that there are such-and-such emotions and not others - this is…evidence of the factitious 
character of human existence’,8 so too with the imaginary. To circumvent this problem, 
alongside the essentialist method is an existential analysis, to allow for the facticity9 of the 
3 
imaginary. 
2. Making Sense of the Imaginary. 
To give a sense to the imaginary, we can begin with a simple characterization of ‘the act of 
imagination [as] a magical act’,10 as Sartre puts it, ‘an incantation destined to make the 
objects of one’s thought, the thing one desires, appear in such a way that one can take 
possession of it’.11 In the performance of an imaging act the world appears in magical mode, 
the given laws of nature no longer apply, the unpredictable and the spontaneous occur, both 
characteristics of the mental (and it is a necessary condition of the imaginary that it is 
mental). The magical is ‘an irrational synthesis of spontaneity and passivity… an inert 
activity, a consciousness rendered passive’.12 For a passive, inert state to produce a 
spontaneous act there is a magical connection,13 for the second is a consequence of the first, 
but cannot be the cause of it. 
When in love, for instance, consciousness has to infuse itself with a sustaining amatory 
mood, for love is an attitude, directed toward the beloved. But for this to occur the word love 
has to be invoked, a means not so much of getting in touch with the inner feelings of being in 
8 Ibid., p. 94. 
9 Sartre’s term for ‘a pure apprehension of the self as a factual existence’. (Jean -Paul Sartre, Being and 
Nothingness (London: Routledge, 1972), p. 338). 
10 Ibid. 1, p. 125. 
11 Ibid. 
12 Ibid. 2, p. 85. 
13 An ‘emanation’. (Jean-Paul Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego (New York: Hill and Wang, 1960), p. 67).
love, but of constituting those feelings in a loving attitude. When Andrew Marvell, in ‘The 
Definition of Love’, wrote: ‘My Love…was begotten by Despair/Upon Impossibility’,14 he is 
not defining love but conceptualising his own love, to consider it and appropriate it, the 
articulation of words enabling the conjuring up of images by consciousness, the latter placing 
itself within an emotional atmosphere connected with such images; his intoxicated soul thus 
4 
conveyed to another sphere of existence. 
Words therefore play a significant part in the imaginary, but what does a word like love 
really achieve? The poet responds to his erotic obsession by conceptualizing it, appropriating 
it in notions composed in an act of reflection. Were he not a poet he could have opted for 
some more inane enunciation, within the seclusion of his own mind, of the words 
corresponding to such notions, the words then being just words, inert things. Having thus 
renounced his capacity to conceptualize he is unable to appropriate the requisite viewpoint on 
his situation, through reflecting on its salient characteristics; instead he assumes an inertness 
that arrests any attempt toward understanding this situation. But in either case, when the 
lover reflects on his love all that is given to him is a momentary experience, a feeling, toward 
an object; everything else is inference, or interpretation, that is, the imaginary is constituted 
by the subject. 
But, it may be asked, what if the lover is disposed to have that same feeling again and again 
over a long period, and is conceptualisation required to turn the feeling into love? Such a 
disposition, however, is a pattern of behaviour unified by an inert state, love, but this state is 
something apart from the repeated feelings themselves, these latter being the phenomena that 
are immediately given to consciousness and that constitute the love in the first place. And the 
feelings have to be constituted as loving feelings, by invoking the word love.15 Reflection 
14 Andrew Marvell, ‘The Definition of Love’, in The Complete Poems (London: Penguin, 2005), p. 49. 
15 The word love is needed to produce the thought that one is in love, as was understood by Stendhal, for whom 
love was not discovered, but created. In The Charterhouse of Parma, Mosca, who loves Sanseverina, observes
can therefore be certain about the feelings, but the state of love itself is always open to 
5 
doubt.16 
Having given sense to the imaginary, I can now reflectively access an image. 
3. Reflecting on the Imaginary. 
It may be objected, however, that to reflect upon an image is to change the image reflected 
upon. But this presupposes of consciousness that it is a kind of container, with events or 
states as contents, (Fig. 1.1),17 yet such a container could not reflect upon its own contents. 
Rather, if I imagine the woman I love, the imaginary consciousness is in a particular mode of 
directedness toward an object, the woman I love, (Fig.1.2).18 Consciousness is of an object 
that is external to it: it is not a thing but a relation to an object, the latter thereby maintaining 
its integrity in eidetic reflection. 
And an image is not a thing traversing consciousness, it is a relation initiated by the 
imaging activity of consciousness as it directs itself toward an object. Whether I am 
imagining the woman I love, or perceiving her, there is in each case a logical relation 
between the mode of intending and its intentional object, the latter occupying a realm of non-accidental 
possibilities, for what is present in a perceptual intentional object is not necessarily 
present in an imaginative intentional object. 
Suppose I see Jessie Matthews,19 she is there, the perceptual object gives itself as 
overflowing, whereas both a photograph and a portrait of Jessie Matthews, (Fig. 2), can 
‘serve as representatives of the absent object’, as Sartre explains, ‘without managing however 
the coach carrying her away with Fabrizio and says: ‘If the word Love comes up between them, I’m lost’. 
(Quoted in Jean-Paul Sartre, What is Literature? (New York: Philosophical Library, Inc., 1949), pp. 23 – 24). 
16 This explains how it can be that I may be mistaken about being in love, without needing to posit an 
unconscious. 
17 The representationalist thesis, held by, among others, John Locke, and Sigmund Freud. 
18 The intentionality thesis, held by, among others, Edmund Husserl, and Jean-Paul Sartre. 
19 An actress from the 1920s and 1930s; my choice of image is entirely arbitrary.
to suspend that characteristic of the objects of an imaging consciousness: absence’.20 But 
whereas the portrait, though recognizable, distorts the face, the nose is too long, the eyes 
lifeless, in the photograph the divine spheres of the eyes manifest an expression of an 
enigmatic melancholia; I ask myself, what is she thinking? 
a representation of the woman I love 
1. 2. 
my mind (represented the arrow of consciousness the object intended 
as a container) (representing the intending) (the woman I lo ve) 
Fig. 1 
This procedure can thus be seen to make use of a mutual connection to the object, which 
Sartre designates the ‘analogon’, in place of a direct perception ‘I make use of a certain 
matter that acts as an analagon, as an equivalent of perception’.21 Imaging consciousness 
reaches its object by means of this analogon that it gives itself, or is given to it. That is, the 
analogon is some kind of thing, perhaps a photograph, a drawing, or a mental image conjured 
up by consciousness itself. And I can reach the essence of the image only insofar as the 
imagined appearance of the object implies a mental given, whatever material is acting as an 
analogon. However, the image is not the analogon, it is the constituting of the analogon, or 
the meaning that consciousness confers on the analogon in constituting it as it is thus 
constituted. To interiorize the image would be to misread the image. 
6 
20 Ibid. 1, p. 20. 
21 Ibid., p. 18.
Fig. 2 
Jessie Matthews 
An act of imaging is, however, unlike perceiving, because an image is not a random 
impression brought about by some enigmatic law of association. It is true that there are 
images that do not appear as a consequence of a conscious decision. Their source is 
unknown, their relevance to my present preoccupations unclear, they give an impression of 
extending throughout consciousness, disposing me to regard object and image has having 
equivalent determinants. But though a thing may suddenly manifest itself, for that thing to 
become image it must be re-apprehended within a new imaging attitude expressed as such. 
At times consciousness has relaxed attitudes, in reverie, for example, but for a thing to be 
conscious, and to have continuity thereby, it has to mean something, and for this to be 
possible it has to be engaged in a development of thinking. 
Image and percept are both spatial, in their different ways, and have the same object, but 
the object as perceived is of infinite determinants, whereas the object as imaged gives all it 
possesses at once, its determinants finite. And given that my relation to this object is 
confined to its original materializations, I do not observe it; I can only contemplate it without 
7
expanding my knowledge of it.22 It holds no surprises, restricted to whatever determinants 
obtained at its inception, lacking any possibility of development. But if the imaginary is 
closed in upon itself in this manner, how can it be presented as ‘surpassing the real’? The 
relation between the imaginary and knowledge needs further clarifying. 
8 
4. Knowing the Imaginary 
But here we encounter a problem, because if consciousness is of its object, the object is at a 
distance from consciousness, the latter at a distance from itself. A pre-reflective distance, 
however, affords a weaker sort of distancing, (consciousness (of), Fig. 3),23 a minimal self-awareness 
consciousness has of itself, not treating itself as an object, (consciousness of). To 
use Sartre’s example: ‘It is very possible that I have no [reflective] consciousness of counting 
[my cigarettes]. Then I do not know myself as counting’, but ‘if anyone should ask, ‘What 
are you doing there?’’ I should reply at once, ‘I am counting’’.24 Of counting he is pre-reflectively 
aware, but his counting is not an object of consciousness. 
Consciousness is therefore distant from the object but not from its images, because these 
are merely relations to the object. The objects of imaging and perceiving are the same 
objects, but with different characteristics; they both minister to a theme and objective, but the 
thematic continuity created by consciousness in the light of them bears a different meaning, a 
consequence of various attitudes and the relational types of consciousness of the world 
contained within these attitudes. And an image requires an imaging directedness; the relation 
between the underlying knowledge that orientates images and the images themselves is 
therefore not an external relation. Knowledge informs the image with meaning and an 
internal consistency that allows it to appear and preserve itself. However meagre the image, 
22 A ‘quasi-observation’. (Ibid., p. 8). 
23 Ibid. 9, p. xxx. 
24 Ibid., p. xxix.
it does possess a collection of determinants that do not indicate numberless other 
determinants, but immediately present it as restricted. 
9 
(of) 
of 
consciousness of 
consciousness (of) 
Fig. 3 
In the absence of the woman I love I see her face, and I know it is her because it is to her 
that I direct my attention. But the nature of this knowledge that traverses the image of an 
imaging attitude differs from that of a conceptualizing attitude, because if I imagine the 
woman I love I am self-evidentially guaranteed my object, at no risk of being surprised to 
find out it is not her after all, which can happen with perception. Now, given that all 
knowledge is conceptual, the ability to apply suitable concepts to a thing constitutes 
knowledge of that thing, the imaginary itself is not knowledge, but it is traversed by a 
knowledge that is immediate. Consciousness therefore begins with conception and then 
assumes an attitude which presupposes conception while differing from it depending on 
whether it has an imaging intentional structure or a perceiving intentional structure. 
Consciousness is thus pre-reflectively aware of an imaging act, this latter lacking a theme 
that can be thought of as knowledge, but the object of my affections is there, though not as an 
object of reflection. And then her image is suddenly enhanced, I have her all at once in a 
single intentional act, and the knowledge that informs the image attributes to her the 
minimum of characteristics by which her image is unambiguous to me, though it is intuitive,
unlike the knowledge that informs perception. But this aspect of consciousness’s imaging is 
a denial of the real, or an act of surpassing, but in what way does such an act serve a 
consciousness momentarily submitting to it, without being completely disoriented by it? 
10 
5. Living Through the Imaginary 
An image, unlike a percept, is formed when consciousness directs itself toward an object that 
it considers as not there, it is a presentation of the object as not there, it is a relation that is 
lived through by consciousness, it is a phenomenon of consciousness, not an object in 
consciousness. The image of the woman I love is given as not present to intuition, she is not 
‘non-intuitive’ but ‘intuitive-absent’,25 as Sartre puts it. The image is consciousness imaging 
the woman I love, it merely indicates a sensuous intuition that cannot occur. The woman I 
love herself I cannot caress, presented as she is at not being at such a distance, in such a 
position: ‘However lively, appealing, strong the image, it gives its object as not being’.26 I 
can imagine the woman I love as far away, or even as non-existent. 
However, my consciousness could only adopt such a non-committal attitude through its 
own creative spontaneity, a creative act that posits a denial of the world itself, rather than a 
particular denial. For example, I can imagine with the intent to imagine, to deny reality, an 
act that has conflicting consequences. Suppose I am missing the woman I love and I 
endeavour to imaginatively call up her face. I pay the price of causing her face to appear, 
apprehending that it is her image only, and I am frustrated in my attempt to satisfy my desire 
for her presence, a disappointment constantly revived by my efforts to sustain her image. But 
suppose I am merely daydreaming, producing imaginary faces for the sake of amusement. I 
25 Ibid. 1, p. 14. 
26 Ibid.
am then no longer preoccupied with the one face of the woman I love, I am instead employed 
in imagining imaginary faces, and am thus detached in my relations with them. 
But this latter is not such a serious pursuit for me, for I am free of the pangs of an absent 
love, and the detachment I feel is due to an absence of any particular objective. In fact, I am 
evading the difficulty I might encounter in the real world had I a real world objective. In a 
condition of dreamy abstraction I am not interested in any particular thing, but repel the 
world in an attitude of disinterestedness.27 Imagination is the ‘‘irrealizing’ function of 
consciousness’,28 the imaginary is the ‘irreal object’,29 and I am active in realizing this irreal 
appearance; that is, living through the irreal, beguiled by the imaginary, I can irrealize 
myself; for example, I can image and mimic a coital act that has an irreal object, the woman I 
11 
love, while knowing she is not there. 
While engaged thus, the fabricated nature of my behaviour is still at least pre-reflectively at 
hand, so to speak, and yet my inclination is still to repel any promptings towards realistic 
behaviour. But this is a mode of imaginary pre-reflective reflectivity that I will, and I live 
through, as an evasion of the world, and which is more threatening to me than an unreflective 
dreamy behaviour that I am forever forewarned about. I follow the guidance of my own 
fabrications, and just as I may become passionately bedevilled by an emotional attitude, so 
too I may by an imaginary attitude, a recurring behavioural evasiveness. 
But the feelings I experience in encountering images are essentially unlike those I 
experience before the objects themselves; I have to perform them, to try and go through with 
them, to affect a suffering caused by them.30 But it is certainly easier to live through the 
27 The imaginary is always motivated by a situation, however, but how this works in practice is so complicated 
and unpredictable that it evades theory. For example, for myself philosophy is always in the air, whatever the 
situation, (Fig. 4). 
28 Ibid. 1, p. 3. 
29 Ibid., p. 125. That is, an object as imaged by consciousness, not an unreal object, (one that could exist but 
does not). An important point, missed by White: ‘It may be because what is imagined is not necessarily real or 
present that…Sartre…thought of what is imagined as necessarily not real or present . (Alan R. White, The 
Language of Imagination (London: Blackwell, 1990), p. 188). On the contrary, the imagined is not not real. 
30 ‘Quasi feelings’, counterparts to ‘quasi observations’.
imaginary, it having rendered my feelings less complicated; so even a normal person like 
myself can encounter problems in reconnecting with reality, even when the object made 
12 
uncomplicated is the woman I love. 
Fig. 4 
Excursion into Philosophy 
Edward Hopper 
But it may be objected that our eidetic descriptions feed upon what Wittgenstein terms ‘a 
one-sided diet: [that] nourishes one’s thinking with only one kind of example… doesn’t our 
understanding reach beyond all the examples?’’31 Do hallucinatory images, for example, 
reach beyond our eidetic descriptions of the constituent elements of the image, like 
Macbeth’s dagger?: 
31 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (London: Blackwell, 1978), §593, p. 155.
13 
…Come, let me clutch thee - 
I have thee not, and yet I see thee still! 
Art thou not, fatal vision, sensible 
To feeling as to sight?32 
Macbeth’s image presents itself as open to sensory apprehension to the extent that he clutches 
at it. His description of the image endows it with the characteristics of a percept: 
I see thee yet, in form as palpable 
As this which now I draw.33 
But Macbeth has to perform a fictive act in order to realize himself, clutching at an imaginary 
dagger in order to insert himself into the real world, upon which he wishes to act but to which 
he is ill-adapted. Attuned to the horror of it, he aspires towards a consistency with his ‘fatal’ 
vision: 
Thou marshall’st me the way that I was going, 
And such an instrument I was to use.- 
Mine eyes are made the fools o’the other senses, 
Or else worth all the rest.34 
The dagger seemingly floating before him and leading him to his victim, he actively pursues 
his path, indicative of a man who knows he has ‘black and deep desires’.35 He is not a 
captive of the imaginary, he is exploiting the imaginary to reach reality and to become real 
32 William Shakespeare, Macbeth (London: Penguin, 1967), p. 73. 
33 Ibid. 
34 Ibid. 
35 Ibid., p. 64.
himself. The imaginary is always motivated by one situation or another, but once it offers up 
to Macbeth the irreal stuff of its productions, he can make them as necessary, or otherwise, 
14 
however much he likes. 
Fig. 5 
Lady Macbeth receives the daggers 
Henry Fuseli 
But what of Macbeth’s disjunctive argument that either the dagger does not exist, a false 
perception, or the vision presents a higher truth? This latter possibility is ruled out by 
Macbeth’s dissatisfaction with the image, of the kind of which Sartre describes: ‘I leave no 
time for the image to develop according to its own laws… the laws of development belonging
to the image are frequently confused with the laws of the essence being considered’.36 The 
imaginary dagger, rather than attempting to render its own essence as intuitive, is produced to 
serve as an intermediary goal for Macbeth, a goal achieved as he continuously mimes his 
feelings and exteriorizes them so as to give them the consistency which he knows they ought 
to have. And the value of resorting to this particular image is determined by Macbeth’s 
peculiar difficulty, but it remains unproductive, an object given in the form of an image is 
closed in upon itself, never containing more than whatever consciousness places in it. 
Macbeth’s hallucinatory dagger teaches him nothing, it represents to him only his own 
avowals, conveniently rendering his questions forever unanswerable. 
An imaginary act, for Sartre, ‘takes the imaged form when it wants to be intuitive, when it 
wants to ground its affirmations on the sight of an object. In that case, it tries to make the 
object appear before it, to see it, or better still to possess it. But this attempt… is always a 
failure: the objects are affected with the character of irreality’.37 The imaginary thus assists 
thinking as it confronts a complication, but we sense its irreality as we enquire into its 
meaning, for have we not determined its meaning already? Has the Sartrean thesis not led us 
15 
to a paradox? 
6. The Paradox of the Imaginary 
What the paradox is exactly can be clarified if we investigate the irrealizing capacity of 
consciousness further. I can realize the woman I love in the past by directing my 
consciousness to past events in order to find among them the kiss she gave me, a kiss that 
does not thereby become irreal, just past. Or I can isolate this kiss, desist from living it as 
real, disconnect it from the real. But then this past kiss as it could have been is only 
36 Ibid. 1, p 119. 
37 Ibid., p. 122.
obtainable to me within the scope of reality as a whole, the latter retained at a distance as I 
deny and surpass it; as I search for it I deny the real time accessible to me. The image of the 
kiss has thereby a timeless appearance, like a work of art that denies reality while revealing it, 
16 
(Fig. 6); it is presented as irreal. 
Fig. 6 
The Kiss 
Pablo Picasso 
But the formation of images, manifesting consciousness’s active ability to escape from the 
thrall of a perceptual existence and passivity, is a poor sort of liberation from the real if the 
denial through imaging is just imaging for its own sake, consciousness in the thrall of its own 
productions, the latter unreceptive to the requirements of consciousness to place a value on its
own existence. In love, on the other hand, the imaginary assumes especial importance as the 
lover looks for another that she can mould into any form in accordance with her amatory 
desires, that can offer her a look free of antagonism, that can favour her with preference, and 
17 
can reflect back to her her own avowals. 
Fig. 7 
Metamorphosis of Narcissus 
Salvador Dali, 1937 
And yet the lover still senses the vanity of love because she senses its irreality, produced by 
her own irrealization. Like Narcissus falling in love with his own image,38 alarmed by the 
presence of impure carnal existents, directing his attention to his own reflection in a stream, 
admiring endlessly his own allure reflected back to him. An irreal existence, allurement 
circumscribed by itself, Narcissus captivated by a delicate image that would disperse into 
38 The irreal is sensed in a way that the unreal is not, an important point missed by Kearney: ‘The narcissistic 
lover is infatuated with nothing other than himself. This gives rise to an ambivalent affection that cannot 
actually be felt (since it is no longer another person that moves me but my own fictional construct)’. (Richard 
Kearney, The Wake of Imagination (London: Routledge, 1998), p. 232). But the affection Narcissus has toward 
himself as beloved object is felt, its irreality is sensed; and the lover in love with another is in the same way 
moved by her own fictional (imaginary) construct (while sensing its irreality).
nothing were he to attempt to clutch it. But if the lover instead endeavours to brave, not an 
image, but a reality never-ending in its capacity to surprise, she becomes the beloved’s thrall; 
no longer endeavouring to possess but to constantly discover her beloved. 
For Sartre this indicates that ‘the imagination is not an empirical power added to 
consciousness, but is the whole of consciousness as it realizes its freedom’.39 There is a 
permanent possibility of going beyond the consciousness which intends reality ‘towards a 
particular imaging consciousness that is like the inverse side of the situation and in relation to 
which the situation is defined’.40 However, Sartre defines situations as ‘the different 
immediate modes of apprehension of the real as a world’,41 they are not merely interactions 
between the real and the imaginary, they are products of the imaginary. But if ‘every 
concrete and real situation of consciousness in the world is pregnant with the imaginary’, as 
the Sartrean thesis states, what then counts as a ‘concrete and real situation’? Imaginary 
events indicate more than a directional change from the real to the mental, they acquire 
ambiguity, for imaging is not constituted on the basis of natural laws; and consciousness can 
18 
surpass itself because it is real. 
‘Can we conceive of a consciousness that would never imagine’, Sartre asks, ‘and that 
would be entirely absorbed in its intuitions of the real’42 Only insofar as the woman I love 
cannot be actually present to me, am I able to imagine her as absent. That is, ‘an image is… 
always the world denied from a certain point of view’.43 And yet, because an image cannot 
appear without indicating its absence, we sense its irreality, it always disappoints; but if a 
point of view is itself a product of the imaginary, it must always disappoint. 
Consciousness is a relation to the real, the latter surpassed through its imaginary function, 
enabling the surpassing of everything existent, a grasping of the latter as real by disengaging 
39 Ibid. 1, p. 186. 
40 Ibid., p. 187. 
41 Ibid., p. 185. The real, taken as obvious, is merely invoked, without explanation, as in the Sartrean thesis. 
42 Ibid. 1, p. 179. 
43 Ibid., pp. 184 – 185.
itself from it, allowing it to grasp the particular meaning of the situation, itself produced by 
the imaginary function, in which reality appears to it. ‘There could be no realizing 
consciousness without imaging consciousness, and vice versa’.44 But given the essential 
directedness of consciousness, a disengagement from the real is only possible through a 
change of direction to some other thing, this latter a product of the imaginary. 
But given that consciousness can never ignore the real, surely this indicates that the 
imaginary is not itself constitutive of reality, although it must be thematically constitutive of 
the objects of our action. With this interplay of engagement and denial consciousness 
becomes a subject that constitutes the world as meaningful. But in eidetic reflection 
consciousness was isolated from the world in order to consider its essential structures of 
directedness toward the world; and the result indicated a consciousness in the world pregnant 
with the imaginary, but as part of that world it is itself a product of the imaginary. How 
could I then engage with a psychology that characterizes the imaginary with a necessity that 
makes it comprehensible, if my feeling of existence is continually accompanied with an 
irreality sense. In such a set-up, how could I ever know who I am, the real me? 
The imaginary function serves as a means toward an end, self-knowledge perhaps, but as a 
product of the imaginary, that is, as truly self-creating, it can only take hold of its own 
irrealizations, and is thereby incapable of effecting the real. If it suppresses the real, the 
imaging subject irrealizes itself. If it suppresses itself to give value to the real, the imaging 
subject submits itself to an impersonal knowledge of itself. In either case consciousness loses 
itself in supressing its relation to the world, either by suppressing the world or its distance 
19 
from it. 
44 Ibid., p. 188.
7. Conclusion: The Treachery of Images 
But rather than supposing there to be a contradiction at the heart of the Sartrean thesis, the 
paradox could perhaps be made less paradoxical through a reappraisal of what is meant by 
the real, and of a real situation, as opposed to an imaginary one. For example, in section 2 it 
was suggested that the articulation of words are needed to provoke the imaginary into the 
direction of constituting of my own feelings, and in section 5 imaging consciousness emerged 
as an unstable relation. But so is the semantic relation between thought and words. I used as 
an example of an imaging relation imagining the woman I love; the woman I love is a 
singular term, with singular terms I touch the world as closely as I ever can.45 But in general 
there is very little relation between an object and that which represents it, be it a word or 
20 
image. 
For example, I can deny that an image of a pipe is a pipe, (Fig. 8), thereby using imaginary 
evidence itself to refute a demonstration of the imaginary,46 and not only can the analogon of 
a pipe not be smoked, neither can the word pipe. A real pipe is a pipe that functions as a 
pipe. But if this is the basis of the identity of a real thing, so too, it would seem, is it of an 
irreal thing.47 And yet the latter is affected by the arbitrariness that we find between word 
and image; that which threatens my confidence in language is now threatening my confidence 
in the imaginary. But it is the very clarity of language that is the source of this threat,48 as it 
is the very obviousness of the real that is now threatening my understanding of the imaginary. 
45 As Davidson says, ‘what touches singular terms touches what they touch, and that is everything: quantifiers, 
variables, predicates, connectives’. (Donald Davidson, ‘On Saying That’, in Synthese (Dordrecht, Holland: D. 
Reidel Publishing Co., 1968 – 1969), pp. 130 – 146), pp. 130 -131). 
46 Which suggests that using the imaginary as a philosophical device in explicating the imaginary, through 
eidetic reflection, leads to situations that are, if not quite paradoxical, at least disorienting. 
47 The problem is that the precise ontological status (if I may speak of reality in such terms) of the irreal, being 
neither real nor unreal, is unclear; and I can see no way of making it more clear. 
48 The meaning of this is not a pipe is clear enough, but the context in which it is expressed disorientates.
This is because Sartre, the irreal notwithstanding, takes the position of previous philosophers 
in characterising the imaginary through a referral to what is real, the latter taken as obvious.49 
Fig. 8 
La Trahison des Images 
René Magritte 
Without knowing what the real is we cannot know what a ‘real situation of consciousness’ 
is, and how it differs from an imaginary situation, and, because of this ambiguity concerning 
a situation, we have our paradox, that the imaginary, perhaps uniquely, is self-created. In 
conclusion, I suggest that the Sartrean thesis has found support in this exercise in eidetic 
reflection, but with the proviso that it is our sense of the vitality of the real, whatever that 
49 John Locke, for instance; imaginary ideas ‘have no foundation in nature, nor have any conformity with that 
reality of being to which they are tacitly referred, as to their archetypes’. (John Locke, An Essay Concerning 
Human Understanding, Vol 1 (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1959). p. 497). 
21
may be, that informs our sense of the irreal; as any practitioner of the art technique of 
trompe-l'oeil50 knows, as they exploit this sense of the real to surpass the real, (Fig. 9). 
Fig. 9 
Escaping Criticism 
Pere Borrell de Caso 
22 
50 Realistic imagery creating illusory imagery.
23 
Bibliography 
Davidson, Donald, ‘On Saying That’, in Synthese (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing 
Co., 1968 – 1969), pp. 130 – 146. 
Descartes, René, ‘Meditations on First Philosophy’, in Philosophical Writings, Vol. II, 
translated by John Cottingham (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). 
Jeanson, Francis, Sartre and the Problem of Morality, translated by Robert V. Stone (Indiana: 
Indiana University Press, 1980). 
Kearney, Richard, The Wake of Imagination (London: Routledge, 1998). 
Marvell, Andrew, The Complete Poems (London: Penguin, 2005). 
Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Vol 1 (New York: Dover 
Publications, Inc., 1959). 
Sartre, Jean-Paul, Being and Nothingness: An Essay in Phenomenological Ontology, 
translated by Hazel E. Barnes (London: Routledge, 1972). 
Sartre, Jean-Paul, Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions, translated by Philip Mairet (London: 
Methuen & Co. Ltd, 1962). 
Sartre, Jean-Paul, The Imaginary, translated by Jonathan Webber (London: Routledge, 2004). 
Sartre, Jean-Paul, The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness, 
translated by Robert Kirkpatrick and Forrest Williams (New York: Hill and Wang, 1960). 
Sartre, Jean-Paul, What is Literature?, translated by Bernard Frechtman (New York: 
Philosophical Library, Inc., 1949). 
Shakespeare, William, Macbeth (London: Penguin, 1967). 
White, Alan R., The Language of Imagination (London: Blackwell, 1990). 
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe 
(London: Blackwell, 1978). 
Word Count: 6018

More Related Content

What's hot

Meditations On Unity In Duality
Meditations On Unity In DualityMeditations On Unity In Duality
Meditations On Unity In DualityWesley F Revels
 
Transcinema: The purpose, uniqueness, and future of cinema
Transcinema: The purpose, uniqueness, and future of cinemaTranscinema: The purpose, uniqueness, and future of cinema
Transcinema: The purpose, uniqueness, and future of cinemaRobert Beshara
 
Lisa Feldman Barrett: Emotions are Made
Lisa Feldman Barrett: Emotions are MadeLisa Feldman Barrett: Emotions are Made
Lisa Feldman Barrett: Emotions are MadeR. Sosa
 
THE PSYCHOLOGIST AND THE MAGICIAN: SOME GOOD ADVICE ON HOW TO SEE LIFE AS IT ...
THE PSYCHOLOGIST AND THE MAGICIAN: SOME GOOD ADVICE ON HOW TO SEE LIFE AS IT ...THE PSYCHOLOGIST AND THE MAGICIAN: SOME GOOD ADVICE ON HOW TO SEE LIFE AS IT ...
THE PSYCHOLOGIST AND THE MAGICIAN: SOME GOOD ADVICE ON HOW TO SEE LIFE AS IT ...Dr Ian Ellis-Jones
 
PHINEAS P. QUIMBY: THE MODERN WORLD’S FIRST TRUE PSYCHOANALYST
PHINEAS P. QUIMBY: THE MODERN WORLD’S FIRST TRUE PSYCHOANALYSTPHINEAS P. QUIMBY: THE MODERN WORLD’S FIRST TRUE PSYCHOANALYST
PHINEAS P. QUIMBY: THE MODERN WORLD’S FIRST TRUE PSYCHOANALYSTDr Ian Ellis-Jones
 
Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s approach to consciousness
Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s approach to consciousness  Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s approach to consciousness
Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s approach to consciousness DMLab
 
Motiongraphicspowerpoint
MotiongraphicspowerpointMotiongraphicspowerpoint
MotiongraphicspowerpointAshley Ahn
 
Harmony: The joy of 'unity in diversity' beyond apparent duality
Harmony: The joy of 'unity in diversity' beyond apparent duality Harmony: The joy of 'unity in diversity' beyond apparent duality
Harmony: The joy of 'unity in diversity' beyond apparent duality Divyanshi Chugh
 
Eternity and on immortality. episode 2.
Eternity and on immortality. episode 2.Eternity and on immortality. episode 2.
Eternity and on immortality. episode 2.Deepak Somaji-Sawant
 
Complete Dissertation + Front Cover
Complete Dissertation + Front CoverComplete Dissertation + Front Cover
Complete Dissertation + Front CoverJohn Wootton
 
Music & Psychotherapy
Music & PsychotherapyMusic & Psychotherapy
Music & PsychotherapyMadhu Sameer
 
Review of The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis
Review of The Four Fundamental Concepts of PsychoanalysisReview of The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis
Review of The Four Fundamental Concepts of PsychoanalysisShiva Kumar Srinivasan
 
The Illusion of the Self: An interpretation of the short story The Psychologi...
The Illusion of the Self: An interpretation of the short story The Psychologi...The Illusion of the Self: An interpretation of the short story The Psychologi...
The Illusion of the Self: An interpretation of the short story The Psychologi...Dr Ian Ellis-Jones
 
ASSIGNMENT ON PHENOMENOLOGY
ASSIGNMENT ON PHENOMENOLOGYASSIGNMENT ON PHENOMENOLOGY
ASSIGNMENT ON PHENOMENOLOGYPrakash Mallick
 
Phenomenology of husserl
Phenomenology of husserlPhenomenology of husserl
Phenomenology of husserlJerick Serandon
 

What's hot (20)

Meditations On Unity In Duality
Meditations On Unity In DualityMeditations On Unity In Duality
Meditations On Unity In Duality
 
Sense nonsense-merleau-ponty
Sense nonsense-merleau-pontySense nonsense-merleau-ponty
Sense nonsense-merleau-ponty
 
Transcinema: The purpose, uniqueness, and future of cinema
Transcinema: The purpose, uniqueness, and future of cinemaTranscinema: The purpose, uniqueness, and future of cinema
Transcinema: The purpose, uniqueness, and future of cinema
 
Lisa Feldman Barrett: Emotions are Made
Lisa Feldman Barrett: Emotions are MadeLisa Feldman Barrett: Emotions are Made
Lisa Feldman Barrett: Emotions are Made
 
THE PSYCHOLOGIST AND THE MAGICIAN: SOME GOOD ADVICE ON HOW TO SEE LIFE AS IT ...
THE PSYCHOLOGIST AND THE MAGICIAN: SOME GOOD ADVICE ON HOW TO SEE LIFE AS IT ...THE PSYCHOLOGIST AND THE MAGICIAN: SOME GOOD ADVICE ON HOW TO SEE LIFE AS IT ...
THE PSYCHOLOGIST AND THE MAGICIAN: SOME GOOD ADVICE ON HOW TO SEE LIFE AS IT ...
 
Meditation
MeditationMeditation
Meditation
 
PHINEAS P. QUIMBY: THE MODERN WORLD’S FIRST TRUE PSYCHOANALYST
PHINEAS P. QUIMBY: THE MODERN WORLD’S FIRST TRUE PSYCHOANALYSTPHINEAS P. QUIMBY: THE MODERN WORLD’S FIRST TRUE PSYCHOANALYST
PHINEAS P. QUIMBY: THE MODERN WORLD’S FIRST TRUE PSYCHOANALYST
 
THE HEALING POWER OF POETRY
THE HEALING POWER OF POETRYTHE HEALING POWER OF POETRY
THE HEALING POWER OF POETRY
 
Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s approach to consciousness
Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s approach to consciousness  Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s approach to consciousness
Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s approach to consciousness
 
Motiongraphicspowerpoint
MotiongraphicspowerpointMotiongraphicspowerpoint
Motiongraphicspowerpoint
 
Harmony: The joy of 'unity in diversity' beyond apparent duality
Harmony: The joy of 'unity in diversity' beyond apparent duality Harmony: The joy of 'unity in diversity' beyond apparent duality
Harmony: The joy of 'unity in diversity' beyond apparent duality
 
Eternity and on immortality. episode 2.
Eternity and on immortality. episode 2.Eternity and on immortality. episode 2.
Eternity and on immortality. episode 2.
 
Complete Dissertation + Front Cover
Complete Dissertation + Front CoverComplete Dissertation + Front Cover
Complete Dissertation + Front Cover
 
Music & Psychotherapy
Music & PsychotherapyMusic & Psychotherapy
Music & Psychotherapy
 
Review of The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis
Review of The Four Fundamental Concepts of PsychoanalysisReview of The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis
Review of The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis
 
Example
ExampleExample
Example
 
The Illusion of the Self: An interpretation of the short story The Psychologi...
The Illusion of the Self: An interpretation of the short story The Psychologi...The Illusion of the Self: An interpretation of the short story The Psychologi...
The Illusion of the Self: An interpretation of the short story The Psychologi...
 
B0323012014
B0323012014B0323012014
B0323012014
 
ASSIGNMENT ON PHENOMENOLOGY
ASSIGNMENT ON PHENOMENOLOGYASSIGNMENT ON PHENOMENOLOGY
ASSIGNMENT ON PHENOMENOLOGY
 
Phenomenology of husserl
Phenomenology of husserlPhenomenology of husserl
Phenomenology of husserl
 

Viewers also liked

Major 20th Century Existentialists
Major 20th Century ExistentialistsMajor 20th Century Existentialists
Major 20th Century Existentialistsnancyahenry
 
Existentialist
ExistentialistExistentialist
ExistentialistSyzrl Anwr
 
Existentialist thought
Existentialist thoughtExistentialist thought
Existentialist thoughtAmanda Umanetz
 
Existentialism By Taylor Schimbke & Karma French
Existentialism By Taylor Schimbke & Karma FrenchExistentialism By Taylor Schimbke & Karma French
Existentialism By Taylor Schimbke & Karma FrenchVictoria Arthur
 
Existentialism sartre etc.-
Existentialism sartre etc.-Existentialism sartre etc.-
Existentialism sartre etc.-sagebennet
 
Philosophy of Existentialism
Philosophy of ExistentialismPhilosophy of Existentialism
Philosophy of ExistentialismRenilyn Tanduyan
 
Existentialism A Philosophy
Existentialism A PhilosophyExistentialism A Philosophy
Existentialism A PhilosophyKSmith15
 
Extentialism and Education Part A
Extentialism and Education Part AExtentialism and Education Part A
Extentialism and Education Part AMaria Lorena Guray
 

Viewers also liked (10)

Major 20th Century Existentialists
Major 20th Century ExistentialistsMajor 20th Century Existentialists
Major 20th Century Existentialists
 
Existentialist
ExistentialistExistentialist
Existentialist
 
Existentialist thought
Existentialist thoughtExistentialist thought
Existentialist thought
 
Existentialism By Taylor Schimbke & Karma French
Existentialism By Taylor Schimbke & Karma FrenchExistentialism By Taylor Schimbke & Karma French
Existentialism By Taylor Schimbke & Karma French
 
Existentialism sartre etc.-
Existentialism sartre etc.-Existentialism sartre etc.-
Existentialism sartre etc.-
 
Philosophy of Existentialism
Philosophy of ExistentialismPhilosophy of Existentialism
Philosophy of Existentialism
 
Existentialism A Philosophy
Existentialism A PhilosophyExistentialism A Philosophy
Existentialism A Philosophy
 
Pragmatism
PragmatismPragmatism
Pragmatism
 
Philosophy of Education: Existentialism
Philosophy of Education: ExistentialismPhilosophy of Education: Existentialism
Philosophy of Education: Existentialism
 
Extentialism and Education Part A
Extentialism and Education Part AExtentialism and Education Part A
Extentialism and Education Part A
 

Similar to TheImagination

Chapter i dream have a meaning
Chapter i dream have a meaningChapter i dream have a meaning
Chapter i dream have a meaningdhanesh gabrial
 
GABRIEL MARCEL MYSTERY OF BEING
GABRIEL MARCEL MYSTERY OF BEINGGABRIEL MARCEL MYSTERY OF BEING
GABRIEL MARCEL MYSTERY OF BEINGErwin Victoriano
 
The Philosophy of Time
The Philosophy of TimeThe Philosophy of Time
The Philosophy of TimeDavid Proud
 
JH Toastmasters Speech Two
JH Toastmasters Speech TwoJH Toastmasters Speech Two
JH Toastmasters Speech TwoJohn Heraghty
 
An Anthropology Of Quot Self Quot Pondering On The Use Of The Self-Portr...
An Anthropology Of  Quot  Self  Quot   Pondering On The Use Of The Self-Portr...An Anthropology Of  Quot  Self  Quot   Pondering On The Use Of The Self-Portr...
An Anthropology Of Quot Self Quot Pondering On The Use Of The Self-Portr...Todd Turner
 
The Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
The Human Person and His IntersubjectivityThe Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
The Human Person and His Intersubjectivityjoshuasulfo
 
A difficulty in the path of psycho analysis
A difficulty in the path of psycho analysisA difficulty in the path of psycho analysis
A difficulty in the path of psycho analysisMichel Newman
 
Dream Interpretation and Psychology pp (2)
Dream Interpretation and Psychology pp (2)Dream Interpretation and Psychology pp (2)
Dream Interpretation and Psychology pp (2)Deb Carney
 
The Representation of Freedom in Henry James
The Representation of Freedom in Henry JamesThe Representation of Freedom in Henry James
The Representation of Freedom in Henry JamesDavid Proud
 
The Philosophy of Time
The Philosophy of TimeThe Philosophy of Time
The Philosophy of TimeDavid Proud
 

Similar to TheImagination (14)

Chapter i dream have a meaning
Chapter i dream have a meaningChapter i dream have a meaning
Chapter i dream have a meaning
 
GABRIEL MARCEL MYSTERY OF BEING
GABRIEL MARCEL MYSTERY OF BEINGGABRIEL MARCEL MYSTERY OF BEING
GABRIEL MARCEL MYSTERY OF BEING
 
The Philosophy of Time
The Philosophy of TimeThe Philosophy of Time
The Philosophy of Time
 
JH Toastmasters Speech Two
JH Toastmasters Speech TwoJH Toastmasters Speech Two
JH Toastmasters Speech Two
 
An Anthropology Of Quot Self Quot Pondering On The Use Of The Self-Portr...
An Anthropology Of  Quot  Self  Quot   Pondering On The Use Of The Self-Portr...An Anthropology Of  Quot  Self  Quot   Pondering On The Use Of The Self-Portr...
An Anthropology Of Quot Self Quot Pondering On The Use Of The Self-Portr...
 
The Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
The Human Person and His IntersubjectivityThe Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
The Human Person and His Intersubjectivity
 
A difficulty in the path of psycho analysis
A difficulty in the path of psycho analysisA difficulty in the path of psycho analysis
A difficulty in the path of psycho analysis
 
Essay On Perception
Essay On PerceptionEssay On Perception
Essay On Perception
 
Dream Interpretation and Psychology pp (2)
Dream Interpretation and Psychology pp (2)Dream Interpretation and Psychology pp (2)
Dream Interpretation and Psychology pp (2)
 
Alisha assinment p4
Alisha assinment p4Alisha assinment p4
Alisha assinment p4
 
The Representation of Freedom in Henry James
The Representation of Freedom in Henry JamesThe Representation of Freedom in Henry James
The Representation of Freedom in Henry James
 
The Philosophy of Time
The Philosophy of TimeThe Philosophy of Time
The Philosophy of Time
 
Frankl
FranklFrankl
Frankl
 
Evideon 1 - Corrado Malanga English
Evideon 1  - Corrado Malanga EnglishEvideon 1  - Corrado Malanga English
Evideon 1 - Corrado Malanga English
 

More from David Proud

ImaginativeResistance_DP (1)
ImaginativeResistance_DP (1)ImaginativeResistance_DP (1)
ImaginativeResistance_DP (1)David Proud
 
The Historicity of Self
The Historicity of SelfThe Historicity of Self
The Historicity of SelfDavid Proud
 
Hegel and Spinoza
Hegel and SpinozaHegel and Spinoza
Hegel and SpinozaDavid Proud
 
Hegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyHegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyDavid Proud
 
Hegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyHegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyDavid Proud
 
Hegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyHegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyDavid Proud
 
Hegeland Spinoza
Hegeland SpinozaHegeland Spinoza
Hegeland SpinozaDavid Proud
 

More from David Proud (8)

ImaginativeResistance_DP (1)
ImaginativeResistance_DP (1)ImaginativeResistance_DP (1)
ImaginativeResistance_DP (1)
 
The Historicity of Self
The Historicity of SelfThe Historicity of Self
The Historicity of Self
 
Nietzsche
NietzscheNietzsche
Nietzsche
 
Hegel and Spinoza
Hegel and SpinozaHegel and Spinoza
Hegel and Spinoza
 
Hegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyHegel and Tragedy
Hegel and Tragedy
 
Hegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyHegel and Tragedy
Hegel and Tragedy
 
Hegel and Tragedy
Hegel and TragedyHegel and Tragedy
Hegel and Tragedy
 
Hegeland Spinoza
Hegeland SpinozaHegeland Spinoza
Hegeland Spinoza
 

TheImagination

  • 1. On The Imaginary Power of Liberation – an Existential Phenomenological Analysis Implicit in the writings of Jean-Paul Sartre on the imaginary is a conviction that any psychology must apprehend the human ‘in situation’,1 its methodology grounded in a general principle of inquiry that has an overt practicality, rather than in a conception of human reality that has been, as Sartre claims, ‘described and fixed by an intuition a priori’.2 Such a conviction underlies this phenomenological analysis3 of the Sartrean thesis that ‘every concrete and real situation of consciousness in the world is pregnant with the imaginary in so far as it is always presented as a surpassing of the real’;4 my purpose being to reveal, from the way the imaginary is thus shown to function in consciousness, a paradox at the heart of this 1 thesis. The essay has the following structure: 1. Methodology: Eidetic Reflection, a method that clarifies that which is essential about a phenomenon of the imaginary. 2. Making Sense of the Imaginary, the imaginary is given its fullest sense, so that, 3. Reflecting on the Imaginary, it can be reflected upon to determine its essence. It is not perception, and, 4. Knowing the Imaginary, it is informed by knowledge, but the latter makes no advancement. Therefore, 5. Living Through the Imaginary, the imaginary cannot exemplify reality, but is motivated by the latter, but then, 6. The Paradox of the Imaginary, the imaginary is self-creating if it is to be motivated by real situations that are a product of itself. However, 7. Conclusion: The Treachery of Images, this paradox emerges because Sartre characterizes the imaginary through a referral to the real, the latter taken as obvious. 1 Jean- Paul Sartre, The Imaginary, (London: Routledge, 2004), p. 186. 2 Jean-Paul Sartre, Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions, (London: Methuen & Co. Ltd, 1962), p. 93. 3 Phenomenology follows Descartes on how to avoid error: ‘Whatever method of proof I use, I am always brought back to the fact that it is only what I clearly and distinctly perceive that completely convinces me’. (René Descartes, ‘Meditations’, in Philosophical Writings, Vol. II, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). p.47). That is, neither obscure nor confused, or whatever is immediately given to me, the phenomena; I confine myself to describing these. 4 Ibid. 1, p. 186.
  • 2. 2 1. Methodology: Eidetic Reflection Eidetic reflection is a descriptive method whereby, as Sartre says, we ‘produc[e] images in ourselves, reflect on these images, describe them, which is to say, try to determine and classify their distinctive characteristics’.5 The objective is an imaginary that is indicative of a human reality that is situated, but is something more than merely a description of various givens; the latter being the procedure of traditional psychologies.6 Perhaps such a procedure threatens a naïve Cartesianism, whereby it is supposed that through the performance of some reflective act the phenomenologist can simply describe the object of reflection, despite the very act of description bringing with it the possibility of misdescription. But eidetic reflection begins with a psychological fact, the image, and through a process of imaginatively varying its different aspects, the limitations in this variation are thereby given immediately and with certainty; I then intuit the eidos, or essence, that which cannot be varied, even in imagination, of the object. It investigates the phenomenon through an explication of its essence, and has at least the form of a conceptual analysis, the specifying of the necessary conditions for the correct application of a concept. It may be objected that appropriating the human ‘in situation’ already presupposes a conception of human reality. But this is simply a regulative idea required by the method. As Sartre explains, ‘the various disciplines of phenomenological psychology are regressive, although the ultimate term of their regression is, for them, purely ideal’.7 Although my method will restrict itself to the phenomenon on which I reflect, I will not attain immediate access to it, though I will be guided by a regulative ideal of human reality, with the proviso 5 Ibid. 1, p. 5. 6 For example, psychoanalysis, whereby the image is a ‘material trace, an inanimate element that afterwards plays the role of symbol’. (Ibid. 1, p. 97). As Jeanson says, with these views ‘there is a power in consciousness, but it is not a power of consciousness’. (Francis Jeanson, Sartre and the Problem of Morality (Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1980), p. 25). 7 Ibid. 2, pp. 93 – 94.
  • 3. that, just as Sartre found with his study of the emotions that phenomenology is unable to ‘show that human-reality must necessarily manifest itself in such emotions as it does’, and ‘that there are such-and-such emotions and not others - this is…evidence of the factitious character of human existence’,8 so too with the imaginary. To circumvent this problem, alongside the essentialist method is an existential analysis, to allow for the facticity9 of the 3 imaginary. 2. Making Sense of the Imaginary. To give a sense to the imaginary, we can begin with a simple characterization of ‘the act of imagination [as] a magical act’,10 as Sartre puts it, ‘an incantation destined to make the objects of one’s thought, the thing one desires, appear in such a way that one can take possession of it’.11 In the performance of an imaging act the world appears in magical mode, the given laws of nature no longer apply, the unpredictable and the spontaneous occur, both characteristics of the mental (and it is a necessary condition of the imaginary that it is mental). The magical is ‘an irrational synthesis of spontaneity and passivity… an inert activity, a consciousness rendered passive’.12 For a passive, inert state to produce a spontaneous act there is a magical connection,13 for the second is a consequence of the first, but cannot be the cause of it. When in love, for instance, consciousness has to infuse itself with a sustaining amatory mood, for love is an attitude, directed toward the beloved. But for this to occur the word love has to be invoked, a means not so much of getting in touch with the inner feelings of being in 8 Ibid., p. 94. 9 Sartre’s term for ‘a pure apprehension of the self as a factual existence’. (Jean -Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness (London: Routledge, 1972), p. 338). 10 Ibid. 1, p. 125. 11 Ibid. 12 Ibid. 2, p. 85. 13 An ‘emanation’. (Jean-Paul Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego (New York: Hill and Wang, 1960), p. 67).
  • 4. love, but of constituting those feelings in a loving attitude. When Andrew Marvell, in ‘The Definition of Love’, wrote: ‘My Love…was begotten by Despair/Upon Impossibility’,14 he is not defining love but conceptualising his own love, to consider it and appropriate it, the articulation of words enabling the conjuring up of images by consciousness, the latter placing itself within an emotional atmosphere connected with such images; his intoxicated soul thus 4 conveyed to another sphere of existence. Words therefore play a significant part in the imaginary, but what does a word like love really achieve? The poet responds to his erotic obsession by conceptualizing it, appropriating it in notions composed in an act of reflection. Were he not a poet he could have opted for some more inane enunciation, within the seclusion of his own mind, of the words corresponding to such notions, the words then being just words, inert things. Having thus renounced his capacity to conceptualize he is unable to appropriate the requisite viewpoint on his situation, through reflecting on its salient characteristics; instead he assumes an inertness that arrests any attempt toward understanding this situation. But in either case, when the lover reflects on his love all that is given to him is a momentary experience, a feeling, toward an object; everything else is inference, or interpretation, that is, the imaginary is constituted by the subject. But, it may be asked, what if the lover is disposed to have that same feeling again and again over a long period, and is conceptualisation required to turn the feeling into love? Such a disposition, however, is a pattern of behaviour unified by an inert state, love, but this state is something apart from the repeated feelings themselves, these latter being the phenomena that are immediately given to consciousness and that constitute the love in the first place. And the feelings have to be constituted as loving feelings, by invoking the word love.15 Reflection 14 Andrew Marvell, ‘The Definition of Love’, in The Complete Poems (London: Penguin, 2005), p. 49. 15 The word love is needed to produce the thought that one is in love, as was understood by Stendhal, for whom love was not discovered, but created. In The Charterhouse of Parma, Mosca, who loves Sanseverina, observes
  • 5. can therefore be certain about the feelings, but the state of love itself is always open to 5 doubt.16 Having given sense to the imaginary, I can now reflectively access an image. 3. Reflecting on the Imaginary. It may be objected, however, that to reflect upon an image is to change the image reflected upon. But this presupposes of consciousness that it is a kind of container, with events or states as contents, (Fig. 1.1),17 yet such a container could not reflect upon its own contents. Rather, if I imagine the woman I love, the imaginary consciousness is in a particular mode of directedness toward an object, the woman I love, (Fig.1.2).18 Consciousness is of an object that is external to it: it is not a thing but a relation to an object, the latter thereby maintaining its integrity in eidetic reflection. And an image is not a thing traversing consciousness, it is a relation initiated by the imaging activity of consciousness as it directs itself toward an object. Whether I am imagining the woman I love, or perceiving her, there is in each case a logical relation between the mode of intending and its intentional object, the latter occupying a realm of non-accidental possibilities, for what is present in a perceptual intentional object is not necessarily present in an imaginative intentional object. Suppose I see Jessie Matthews,19 she is there, the perceptual object gives itself as overflowing, whereas both a photograph and a portrait of Jessie Matthews, (Fig. 2), can ‘serve as representatives of the absent object’, as Sartre explains, ‘without managing however the coach carrying her away with Fabrizio and says: ‘If the word Love comes up between them, I’m lost’. (Quoted in Jean-Paul Sartre, What is Literature? (New York: Philosophical Library, Inc., 1949), pp. 23 – 24). 16 This explains how it can be that I may be mistaken about being in love, without needing to posit an unconscious. 17 The representationalist thesis, held by, among others, John Locke, and Sigmund Freud. 18 The intentionality thesis, held by, among others, Edmund Husserl, and Jean-Paul Sartre. 19 An actress from the 1920s and 1930s; my choice of image is entirely arbitrary.
  • 6. to suspend that characteristic of the objects of an imaging consciousness: absence’.20 But whereas the portrait, though recognizable, distorts the face, the nose is too long, the eyes lifeless, in the photograph the divine spheres of the eyes manifest an expression of an enigmatic melancholia; I ask myself, what is she thinking? a representation of the woman I love 1. 2. my mind (represented the arrow of consciousness the object intended as a container) (representing the intending) (the woman I lo ve) Fig. 1 This procedure can thus be seen to make use of a mutual connection to the object, which Sartre designates the ‘analogon’, in place of a direct perception ‘I make use of a certain matter that acts as an analagon, as an equivalent of perception’.21 Imaging consciousness reaches its object by means of this analogon that it gives itself, or is given to it. That is, the analogon is some kind of thing, perhaps a photograph, a drawing, or a mental image conjured up by consciousness itself. And I can reach the essence of the image only insofar as the imagined appearance of the object implies a mental given, whatever material is acting as an analogon. However, the image is not the analogon, it is the constituting of the analogon, or the meaning that consciousness confers on the analogon in constituting it as it is thus constituted. To interiorize the image would be to misread the image. 6 20 Ibid. 1, p. 20. 21 Ibid., p. 18.
  • 7. Fig. 2 Jessie Matthews An act of imaging is, however, unlike perceiving, because an image is not a random impression brought about by some enigmatic law of association. It is true that there are images that do not appear as a consequence of a conscious decision. Their source is unknown, their relevance to my present preoccupations unclear, they give an impression of extending throughout consciousness, disposing me to regard object and image has having equivalent determinants. But though a thing may suddenly manifest itself, for that thing to become image it must be re-apprehended within a new imaging attitude expressed as such. At times consciousness has relaxed attitudes, in reverie, for example, but for a thing to be conscious, and to have continuity thereby, it has to mean something, and for this to be possible it has to be engaged in a development of thinking. Image and percept are both spatial, in their different ways, and have the same object, but the object as perceived is of infinite determinants, whereas the object as imaged gives all it possesses at once, its determinants finite. And given that my relation to this object is confined to its original materializations, I do not observe it; I can only contemplate it without 7
  • 8. expanding my knowledge of it.22 It holds no surprises, restricted to whatever determinants obtained at its inception, lacking any possibility of development. But if the imaginary is closed in upon itself in this manner, how can it be presented as ‘surpassing the real’? The relation between the imaginary and knowledge needs further clarifying. 8 4. Knowing the Imaginary But here we encounter a problem, because if consciousness is of its object, the object is at a distance from consciousness, the latter at a distance from itself. A pre-reflective distance, however, affords a weaker sort of distancing, (consciousness (of), Fig. 3),23 a minimal self-awareness consciousness has of itself, not treating itself as an object, (consciousness of). To use Sartre’s example: ‘It is very possible that I have no [reflective] consciousness of counting [my cigarettes]. Then I do not know myself as counting’, but ‘if anyone should ask, ‘What are you doing there?’’ I should reply at once, ‘I am counting’’.24 Of counting he is pre-reflectively aware, but his counting is not an object of consciousness. Consciousness is therefore distant from the object but not from its images, because these are merely relations to the object. The objects of imaging and perceiving are the same objects, but with different characteristics; they both minister to a theme and objective, but the thematic continuity created by consciousness in the light of them bears a different meaning, a consequence of various attitudes and the relational types of consciousness of the world contained within these attitudes. And an image requires an imaging directedness; the relation between the underlying knowledge that orientates images and the images themselves is therefore not an external relation. Knowledge informs the image with meaning and an internal consistency that allows it to appear and preserve itself. However meagre the image, 22 A ‘quasi-observation’. (Ibid., p. 8). 23 Ibid. 9, p. xxx. 24 Ibid., p. xxix.
  • 9. it does possess a collection of determinants that do not indicate numberless other determinants, but immediately present it as restricted. 9 (of) of consciousness of consciousness (of) Fig. 3 In the absence of the woman I love I see her face, and I know it is her because it is to her that I direct my attention. But the nature of this knowledge that traverses the image of an imaging attitude differs from that of a conceptualizing attitude, because if I imagine the woman I love I am self-evidentially guaranteed my object, at no risk of being surprised to find out it is not her after all, which can happen with perception. Now, given that all knowledge is conceptual, the ability to apply suitable concepts to a thing constitutes knowledge of that thing, the imaginary itself is not knowledge, but it is traversed by a knowledge that is immediate. Consciousness therefore begins with conception and then assumes an attitude which presupposes conception while differing from it depending on whether it has an imaging intentional structure or a perceiving intentional structure. Consciousness is thus pre-reflectively aware of an imaging act, this latter lacking a theme that can be thought of as knowledge, but the object of my affections is there, though not as an object of reflection. And then her image is suddenly enhanced, I have her all at once in a single intentional act, and the knowledge that informs the image attributes to her the minimum of characteristics by which her image is unambiguous to me, though it is intuitive,
  • 10. unlike the knowledge that informs perception. But this aspect of consciousness’s imaging is a denial of the real, or an act of surpassing, but in what way does such an act serve a consciousness momentarily submitting to it, without being completely disoriented by it? 10 5. Living Through the Imaginary An image, unlike a percept, is formed when consciousness directs itself toward an object that it considers as not there, it is a presentation of the object as not there, it is a relation that is lived through by consciousness, it is a phenomenon of consciousness, not an object in consciousness. The image of the woman I love is given as not present to intuition, she is not ‘non-intuitive’ but ‘intuitive-absent’,25 as Sartre puts it. The image is consciousness imaging the woman I love, it merely indicates a sensuous intuition that cannot occur. The woman I love herself I cannot caress, presented as she is at not being at such a distance, in such a position: ‘However lively, appealing, strong the image, it gives its object as not being’.26 I can imagine the woman I love as far away, or even as non-existent. However, my consciousness could only adopt such a non-committal attitude through its own creative spontaneity, a creative act that posits a denial of the world itself, rather than a particular denial. For example, I can imagine with the intent to imagine, to deny reality, an act that has conflicting consequences. Suppose I am missing the woman I love and I endeavour to imaginatively call up her face. I pay the price of causing her face to appear, apprehending that it is her image only, and I am frustrated in my attempt to satisfy my desire for her presence, a disappointment constantly revived by my efforts to sustain her image. But suppose I am merely daydreaming, producing imaginary faces for the sake of amusement. I 25 Ibid. 1, p. 14. 26 Ibid.
  • 11. am then no longer preoccupied with the one face of the woman I love, I am instead employed in imagining imaginary faces, and am thus detached in my relations with them. But this latter is not such a serious pursuit for me, for I am free of the pangs of an absent love, and the detachment I feel is due to an absence of any particular objective. In fact, I am evading the difficulty I might encounter in the real world had I a real world objective. In a condition of dreamy abstraction I am not interested in any particular thing, but repel the world in an attitude of disinterestedness.27 Imagination is the ‘‘irrealizing’ function of consciousness’,28 the imaginary is the ‘irreal object’,29 and I am active in realizing this irreal appearance; that is, living through the irreal, beguiled by the imaginary, I can irrealize myself; for example, I can image and mimic a coital act that has an irreal object, the woman I 11 love, while knowing she is not there. While engaged thus, the fabricated nature of my behaviour is still at least pre-reflectively at hand, so to speak, and yet my inclination is still to repel any promptings towards realistic behaviour. But this is a mode of imaginary pre-reflective reflectivity that I will, and I live through, as an evasion of the world, and which is more threatening to me than an unreflective dreamy behaviour that I am forever forewarned about. I follow the guidance of my own fabrications, and just as I may become passionately bedevilled by an emotional attitude, so too I may by an imaginary attitude, a recurring behavioural evasiveness. But the feelings I experience in encountering images are essentially unlike those I experience before the objects themselves; I have to perform them, to try and go through with them, to affect a suffering caused by them.30 But it is certainly easier to live through the 27 The imaginary is always motivated by a situation, however, but how this works in practice is so complicated and unpredictable that it evades theory. For example, for myself philosophy is always in the air, whatever the situation, (Fig. 4). 28 Ibid. 1, p. 3. 29 Ibid., p. 125. That is, an object as imaged by consciousness, not an unreal object, (one that could exist but does not). An important point, missed by White: ‘It may be because what is imagined is not necessarily real or present that…Sartre…thought of what is imagined as necessarily not real or present . (Alan R. White, The Language of Imagination (London: Blackwell, 1990), p. 188). On the contrary, the imagined is not not real. 30 ‘Quasi feelings’, counterparts to ‘quasi observations’.
  • 12. imaginary, it having rendered my feelings less complicated; so even a normal person like myself can encounter problems in reconnecting with reality, even when the object made 12 uncomplicated is the woman I love. Fig. 4 Excursion into Philosophy Edward Hopper But it may be objected that our eidetic descriptions feed upon what Wittgenstein terms ‘a one-sided diet: [that] nourishes one’s thinking with only one kind of example… doesn’t our understanding reach beyond all the examples?’’31 Do hallucinatory images, for example, reach beyond our eidetic descriptions of the constituent elements of the image, like Macbeth’s dagger?: 31 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (London: Blackwell, 1978), §593, p. 155.
  • 13. 13 …Come, let me clutch thee - I have thee not, and yet I see thee still! Art thou not, fatal vision, sensible To feeling as to sight?32 Macbeth’s image presents itself as open to sensory apprehension to the extent that he clutches at it. His description of the image endows it with the characteristics of a percept: I see thee yet, in form as palpable As this which now I draw.33 But Macbeth has to perform a fictive act in order to realize himself, clutching at an imaginary dagger in order to insert himself into the real world, upon which he wishes to act but to which he is ill-adapted. Attuned to the horror of it, he aspires towards a consistency with his ‘fatal’ vision: Thou marshall’st me the way that I was going, And such an instrument I was to use.- Mine eyes are made the fools o’the other senses, Or else worth all the rest.34 The dagger seemingly floating before him and leading him to his victim, he actively pursues his path, indicative of a man who knows he has ‘black and deep desires’.35 He is not a captive of the imaginary, he is exploiting the imaginary to reach reality and to become real 32 William Shakespeare, Macbeth (London: Penguin, 1967), p. 73. 33 Ibid. 34 Ibid. 35 Ibid., p. 64.
  • 14. himself. The imaginary is always motivated by one situation or another, but once it offers up to Macbeth the irreal stuff of its productions, he can make them as necessary, or otherwise, 14 however much he likes. Fig. 5 Lady Macbeth receives the daggers Henry Fuseli But what of Macbeth’s disjunctive argument that either the dagger does not exist, a false perception, or the vision presents a higher truth? This latter possibility is ruled out by Macbeth’s dissatisfaction with the image, of the kind of which Sartre describes: ‘I leave no time for the image to develop according to its own laws… the laws of development belonging
  • 15. to the image are frequently confused with the laws of the essence being considered’.36 The imaginary dagger, rather than attempting to render its own essence as intuitive, is produced to serve as an intermediary goal for Macbeth, a goal achieved as he continuously mimes his feelings and exteriorizes them so as to give them the consistency which he knows they ought to have. And the value of resorting to this particular image is determined by Macbeth’s peculiar difficulty, but it remains unproductive, an object given in the form of an image is closed in upon itself, never containing more than whatever consciousness places in it. Macbeth’s hallucinatory dagger teaches him nothing, it represents to him only his own avowals, conveniently rendering his questions forever unanswerable. An imaginary act, for Sartre, ‘takes the imaged form when it wants to be intuitive, when it wants to ground its affirmations on the sight of an object. In that case, it tries to make the object appear before it, to see it, or better still to possess it. But this attempt… is always a failure: the objects are affected with the character of irreality’.37 The imaginary thus assists thinking as it confronts a complication, but we sense its irreality as we enquire into its meaning, for have we not determined its meaning already? Has the Sartrean thesis not led us 15 to a paradox? 6. The Paradox of the Imaginary What the paradox is exactly can be clarified if we investigate the irrealizing capacity of consciousness further. I can realize the woman I love in the past by directing my consciousness to past events in order to find among them the kiss she gave me, a kiss that does not thereby become irreal, just past. Or I can isolate this kiss, desist from living it as real, disconnect it from the real. But then this past kiss as it could have been is only 36 Ibid. 1, p 119. 37 Ibid., p. 122.
  • 16. obtainable to me within the scope of reality as a whole, the latter retained at a distance as I deny and surpass it; as I search for it I deny the real time accessible to me. The image of the kiss has thereby a timeless appearance, like a work of art that denies reality while revealing it, 16 (Fig. 6); it is presented as irreal. Fig. 6 The Kiss Pablo Picasso But the formation of images, manifesting consciousness’s active ability to escape from the thrall of a perceptual existence and passivity, is a poor sort of liberation from the real if the denial through imaging is just imaging for its own sake, consciousness in the thrall of its own productions, the latter unreceptive to the requirements of consciousness to place a value on its
  • 17. own existence. In love, on the other hand, the imaginary assumes especial importance as the lover looks for another that she can mould into any form in accordance with her amatory desires, that can offer her a look free of antagonism, that can favour her with preference, and 17 can reflect back to her her own avowals. Fig. 7 Metamorphosis of Narcissus Salvador Dali, 1937 And yet the lover still senses the vanity of love because she senses its irreality, produced by her own irrealization. Like Narcissus falling in love with his own image,38 alarmed by the presence of impure carnal existents, directing his attention to his own reflection in a stream, admiring endlessly his own allure reflected back to him. An irreal existence, allurement circumscribed by itself, Narcissus captivated by a delicate image that would disperse into 38 The irreal is sensed in a way that the unreal is not, an important point missed by Kearney: ‘The narcissistic lover is infatuated with nothing other than himself. This gives rise to an ambivalent affection that cannot actually be felt (since it is no longer another person that moves me but my own fictional construct)’. (Richard Kearney, The Wake of Imagination (London: Routledge, 1998), p. 232). But the affection Narcissus has toward himself as beloved object is felt, its irreality is sensed; and the lover in love with another is in the same way moved by her own fictional (imaginary) construct (while sensing its irreality).
  • 18. nothing were he to attempt to clutch it. But if the lover instead endeavours to brave, not an image, but a reality never-ending in its capacity to surprise, she becomes the beloved’s thrall; no longer endeavouring to possess but to constantly discover her beloved. For Sartre this indicates that ‘the imagination is not an empirical power added to consciousness, but is the whole of consciousness as it realizes its freedom’.39 There is a permanent possibility of going beyond the consciousness which intends reality ‘towards a particular imaging consciousness that is like the inverse side of the situation and in relation to which the situation is defined’.40 However, Sartre defines situations as ‘the different immediate modes of apprehension of the real as a world’,41 they are not merely interactions between the real and the imaginary, they are products of the imaginary. But if ‘every concrete and real situation of consciousness in the world is pregnant with the imaginary’, as the Sartrean thesis states, what then counts as a ‘concrete and real situation’? Imaginary events indicate more than a directional change from the real to the mental, they acquire ambiguity, for imaging is not constituted on the basis of natural laws; and consciousness can 18 surpass itself because it is real. ‘Can we conceive of a consciousness that would never imagine’, Sartre asks, ‘and that would be entirely absorbed in its intuitions of the real’42 Only insofar as the woman I love cannot be actually present to me, am I able to imagine her as absent. That is, ‘an image is… always the world denied from a certain point of view’.43 And yet, because an image cannot appear without indicating its absence, we sense its irreality, it always disappoints; but if a point of view is itself a product of the imaginary, it must always disappoint. Consciousness is a relation to the real, the latter surpassed through its imaginary function, enabling the surpassing of everything existent, a grasping of the latter as real by disengaging 39 Ibid. 1, p. 186. 40 Ibid., p. 187. 41 Ibid., p. 185. The real, taken as obvious, is merely invoked, without explanation, as in the Sartrean thesis. 42 Ibid. 1, p. 179. 43 Ibid., pp. 184 – 185.
  • 19. itself from it, allowing it to grasp the particular meaning of the situation, itself produced by the imaginary function, in which reality appears to it. ‘There could be no realizing consciousness without imaging consciousness, and vice versa’.44 But given the essential directedness of consciousness, a disengagement from the real is only possible through a change of direction to some other thing, this latter a product of the imaginary. But given that consciousness can never ignore the real, surely this indicates that the imaginary is not itself constitutive of reality, although it must be thematically constitutive of the objects of our action. With this interplay of engagement and denial consciousness becomes a subject that constitutes the world as meaningful. But in eidetic reflection consciousness was isolated from the world in order to consider its essential structures of directedness toward the world; and the result indicated a consciousness in the world pregnant with the imaginary, but as part of that world it is itself a product of the imaginary. How could I then engage with a psychology that characterizes the imaginary with a necessity that makes it comprehensible, if my feeling of existence is continually accompanied with an irreality sense. In such a set-up, how could I ever know who I am, the real me? The imaginary function serves as a means toward an end, self-knowledge perhaps, but as a product of the imaginary, that is, as truly self-creating, it can only take hold of its own irrealizations, and is thereby incapable of effecting the real. If it suppresses the real, the imaging subject irrealizes itself. If it suppresses itself to give value to the real, the imaging subject submits itself to an impersonal knowledge of itself. In either case consciousness loses itself in supressing its relation to the world, either by suppressing the world or its distance 19 from it. 44 Ibid., p. 188.
  • 20. 7. Conclusion: The Treachery of Images But rather than supposing there to be a contradiction at the heart of the Sartrean thesis, the paradox could perhaps be made less paradoxical through a reappraisal of what is meant by the real, and of a real situation, as opposed to an imaginary one. For example, in section 2 it was suggested that the articulation of words are needed to provoke the imaginary into the direction of constituting of my own feelings, and in section 5 imaging consciousness emerged as an unstable relation. But so is the semantic relation between thought and words. I used as an example of an imaging relation imagining the woman I love; the woman I love is a singular term, with singular terms I touch the world as closely as I ever can.45 But in general there is very little relation between an object and that which represents it, be it a word or 20 image. For example, I can deny that an image of a pipe is a pipe, (Fig. 8), thereby using imaginary evidence itself to refute a demonstration of the imaginary,46 and not only can the analogon of a pipe not be smoked, neither can the word pipe. A real pipe is a pipe that functions as a pipe. But if this is the basis of the identity of a real thing, so too, it would seem, is it of an irreal thing.47 And yet the latter is affected by the arbitrariness that we find between word and image; that which threatens my confidence in language is now threatening my confidence in the imaginary. But it is the very clarity of language that is the source of this threat,48 as it is the very obviousness of the real that is now threatening my understanding of the imaginary. 45 As Davidson says, ‘what touches singular terms touches what they touch, and that is everything: quantifiers, variables, predicates, connectives’. (Donald Davidson, ‘On Saying That’, in Synthese (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1968 – 1969), pp. 130 – 146), pp. 130 -131). 46 Which suggests that using the imaginary as a philosophical device in explicating the imaginary, through eidetic reflection, leads to situations that are, if not quite paradoxical, at least disorienting. 47 The problem is that the precise ontological status (if I may speak of reality in such terms) of the irreal, being neither real nor unreal, is unclear; and I can see no way of making it more clear. 48 The meaning of this is not a pipe is clear enough, but the context in which it is expressed disorientates.
  • 21. This is because Sartre, the irreal notwithstanding, takes the position of previous philosophers in characterising the imaginary through a referral to what is real, the latter taken as obvious.49 Fig. 8 La Trahison des Images René Magritte Without knowing what the real is we cannot know what a ‘real situation of consciousness’ is, and how it differs from an imaginary situation, and, because of this ambiguity concerning a situation, we have our paradox, that the imaginary, perhaps uniquely, is self-created. In conclusion, I suggest that the Sartrean thesis has found support in this exercise in eidetic reflection, but with the proviso that it is our sense of the vitality of the real, whatever that 49 John Locke, for instance; imaginary ideas ‘have no foundation in nature, nor have any conformity with that reality of being to which they are tacitly referred, as to their archetypes’. (John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Vol 1 (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1959). p. 497). 21
  • 22. may be, that informs our sense of the irreal; as any practitioner of the art technique of trompe-l'oeil50 knows, as they exploit this sense of the real to surpass the real, (Fig. 9). Fig. 9 Escaping Criticism Pere Borrell de Caso 22 50 Realistic imagery creating illusory imagery.
  • 23. 23 Bibliography Davidson, Donald, ‘On Saying That’, in Synthese (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Co., 1968 – 1969), pp. 130 – 146. Descartes, René, ‘Meditations on First Philosophy’, in Philosophical Writings, Vol. II, translated by John Cottingham (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984). Jeanson, Francis, Sartre and the Problem of Morality, translated by Robert V. Stone (Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1980). Kearney, Richard, The Wake of Imagination (London: Routledge, 1998). Marvell, Andrew, The Complete Poems (London: Penguin, 2005). Locke, John, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Vol 1 (New York: Dover Publications, Inc., 1959). Sartre, Jean-Paul, Being and Nothingness: An Essay in Phenomenological Ontology, translated by Hazel E. Barnes (London: Routledge, 1972). Sartre, Jean-Paul, Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions, translated by Philip Mairet (London: Methuen & Co. Ltd, 1962). Sartre, Jean-Paul, The Imaginary, translated by Jonathan Webber (London: Routledge, 2004). Sartre, Jean-Paul, The Transcendence of the Ego: An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness, translated by Robert Kirkpatrick and Forrest Williams (New York: Hill and Wang, 1960). Sartre, Jean-Paul, What is Literature?, translated by Bernard Frechtman (New York: Philosophical Library, Inc., 1949). Shakespeare, William, Macbeth (London: Penguin, 1967). White, Alan R., The Language of Imagination (London: Blackwell, 1990). Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe (London: Blackwell, 1978). Word Count: 6018