SlideShare une entreprise Scribd logo
1  sur  13
Télécharger pour lire hors ligne
Teaching (With) Virtues Through Incorporating Supplemental Instruction
                                    Gregory B. Sadler, ReasonIO
                                             greg@reasonio.com


        What sorts of skills and dispositions do we need to attend to or cultivate in order to render
Supplemental Instruction a highly effective pedagogical resource? There are three likely immediate
answers to this question, responses which do possess their merits in pointing out important factors for
success in implementation of this resource: disciplinary knowledge, pedagogical expertise, and the
broad category of “people skills”. I’ll acknowledge the importance of these shortly, but before doing
that, I’d like to bring up another type of set of skills and dispositions: the virtues, both intellectual and
moral. In the next twenty-five or so minutes, I’ll be sketching out a broadly Aristotelian Virtue Ethics
framework within which I suggest Supplemental Instruction might be very profitably located and
further thought out. I would like to make clear from the start that I’m not proposing that this Virtue
Ethics framework be viewed as a competitor to other good ways of understanding and orienting SI w
focus more thematically on other aspects or dimensions of SI. I’d rather it be seen as a useful
complementary perspective.


        Multiple sets of skills and dispositions are needed or desirable for both Instructors and students
who are Supplemental Instruction leaders or coaches. Expertise in an academic discipline, in what
happens to be the subject matter being studied, is one of these. That almost goes without saying, but it is
worth dwelling on this, since one of the prevalent misconceptions of which we so often have to disabuse
our students is that learning and expertise is largely a matter of acquiring information, rather than of
developing a battery of skills, some general like written communication, critical thinking, and problem
solving, others specific to the subject matter but often susceptible of transfer or analogy to other
contexts when a level of mastery has been attained. Even deeper than skills, and equally important are
dispositions, developed habits, general attitudes, outlooks and approaches, affective orientations and
patterns of desire and emotional response. In one of the main fields in which I work, Critical Thinking,
that field of performance and expertise has long been identified by one of the most rigorous disciplinary
models and self-studies, the APA Delphi Report, as consisting specifically in skills and dispositions.
Within classical Aristotelian philosophy of education, such an assemblage of interlocking and scaffolded
knowledge, skills, and dispositions well-established in the mind of the learner is termed a hexis or
habitus. It becomes as it were a possession rooted in the being of the knower (and doer, actor, producer,


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                       1
communicator) and is, when developed, one type of intellectual virtue, a state of excellence of the
human mind.


        As all of us know, some of us having been schooled by painful experience, there is an art and an
expertise whose product is consistently teaching well. It is different from though does bear affinities
with certain types of disciplinary expertise. One can be a great scholar in a particular field, afire with
palpable and communicable passion for its objects, and yet teach material one knows inside and out in
ways confusing, uninformative, even inscrutable to one’s students. This is a second sort of skills and
desirable dispositions susceptible of being taught, even formalized in certain systems to some degree. A
third is that set which often get called things like “people skills,” not merely a matter of communication
abilities, but the capacity to relate oneself to others, to their ideas, environments, emotions, ideas,
experiences. This third set of skills and dispositions in fact overlaps in part with the second, one reason
why teaching well cannot be routinized, turned into a science, reduced to lesson plans, etc. – the
guardrails of pedagogy. Both sets of skills and dispositions, I should point out, may involve the sort of
habitus specific to disciplinary knowledge. It’s worth noting for the moment that they also involve the
excellence of phronesis, prudentia, or practical wisdom, which I’ll discuss a bit later.


        An ideal instructor develops, possesses, exhibits, integrates, and models well all three of these all
of the time. Real instructors like ourselves, of course, do these more or less well, more or less
consistently, stronger in some areas, at particular times, in certain types of situations than in others,
hopefully improving, reflecting on good or bad experiences, intentions, and outcomes, adding to our
areas of strength and expertise through theoretical study, interaction with our peers, appropriating
useful or engaging resources, putting things into practice, and thoughtful reassessment. As a result – or
better put – through these processes, education occurs, learning takes place within, through, by
students, more or less successfully. Hopefully the students come out of the class not only having learned
disciplinary information at a surface and easily forgotten level, but at the deeper, more retentive and
integrated levels signified when we speak of disciplinary knowledge as a habitus. They might have
developed some initial or additional competencies in people skills or even in pedagogical competency,
depending on what has taken place in the class, what the students themselves have done, participated
in, observed, studied, and reflected upon.


        Adding an SI leader or any sort of intermediary, a Teaching Assistant or a Tutor for instance,
renders these matters more complex, since the intermediary functions as an instructor, albeit at a


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                       2
different level and in different ways, and as a student, albeit a student with a higher, more integrated
grasp of the course material. There’s also the question of the degree to, and the ways which the
instructor teaches, interacts with, and fosters the development of the SI leader, and the feedback about
or insight into the students provided to the instructor by the SI leader who has a unique and useful
vantage point from which to observe and interact with students. With this more complex and
potentially more productive arrangement outlined, we can raise the question of whether what is going
on, what could potentially be going on, what ought to be going on, and what we as instructors would
like to be going on – for these are not the same and can often suffer a disconnect -- can be adequately
conceptualized solely in terms of disciplinary knowledge, pedagogical expertise, and people skills.


        All of these are important, to be sure, but I would like to say that, and to some extent say why
and how, thinking about SI in terms of the family of approaches in moral theory called Virtue Ethics
contributes to developing a yet more adequate understanding of what still more effective use of SI
would look like. So, before doing those things, let me make clear some of the suggestions I am and am
not making. I am suggesting that Virtue Ethics provides a needed complement to other more explicitly
pedagogical-theoretical and less explicitly moral-theoretical approaches. I am not suggesting that
Virtue Ethics is a substitute for other approaches. I am also not saying that the instructor whose
disciplinary competence lies in some other field now also needs to become a disciplinary expert in
Philosophy or Ethics, let alone a specialist in Virtue Ethics. I am saying that some of the typical
components of a Virtue Ethics approach are susceptible of being adopted and appropriated as useful
portions of one’s own approach to effective employment of SI leaders. These components do this in two
ways. There are some ideas or considerations a Virtue Ethics approach provides unlikely to be provided
or even realized as needed in its absence. There are other ideas or considerations already in place, on
the table, which while making good sense in themselves, find themselves further illuminated by a Virtue
Ethics approach, one example of this being practical wisdom ‘s important role in pedagogical expertise
and people skills.


        What I plan to do in this short talk, before opening the floor up to address any questions,
concerns, complaints, and then to engage in dialogue, are four things. I’m going to give a necessarily
very brief overview of Virtue Ethics as a type of moral theory. Then, I’m going to look at the purposes or
ends of SI within that framework. After that, I’m going to discuss which virtues (and vices) are
important to focus upon in order to ensure effective use of SI. Lastly, I’m going to talk a bit about



(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      3
conditions necessary for developing virtues and integrating them with the three other sets of skills and
dispositions.


        So, what is Virtue Ethics? Along with Utilitarianism, Deontological Ethics, Natural Law Ethics,
and Ethics of Care, for examples, Virtue Ethics is one of the main well-established and coherent moral
theories which we teach in Ethics and various Applied Ethics courses. It actually represents an entire
family of moral theories, some of which have been developed in relation or response to each other, so it
includes ethics articulated by ancient philosophers such as Plato, Aristotle, and Cicero, medieval
thinkers like SS. Augustine, Anselm, Thomas Aquinas, and non-western thinkers like Confucius. It also
includes traditions of further interpretation and enquiry continuing these ethics, down to contemporary
thinkers like Alasdair MacIntyre and Martha Nussbaum. One of the distinctive features shared by all of
these various virtue ethics is making virtues and vices -- the array of good and bad moral dispositions
developed as habits over time through actions and choices -- of central consideration in evaluating the
goodness or badness, the rightness or wrongness, the appropriateness or inappropriateness of actions,
emotional responses , intentions and choices, policies and institutions, even of persons. Instead of
simply focusing on conformity to rules discoverable by reason, or following moral or professional codes,
or calculating best outcomes for all or most concerned, or displaying compassion, or even on other
broad ethical principles, Virtue Ethics goes beyond and situates all of these in relation to three other sets
of matters: reframing thinking in terms of horizons of human flourishing, excellence, means and ends;
identifying and understanding the specific range of virtues and vices that need to be cultivated or
rooted out; and determining how virtues and vices are to actually be cultivated or rooted out in actual
practice.


        It makes good sense to start by stepping back momentarily and asking several questions often
overlooked, forgotten, or unsuspected as we go about all our many actions and involvements as
educators. Many of us already routinely ask questions similar in intent though different in scope as an
integral component of our work as educators. When carrying out integrated course design, for
instance, we ask ourselves about broad, big-picture learning goals or objectives for our students as well
as determining what student learning outcomes we want to focus on, and then we think about what
learning activities would provide practice and ways of assessing those outcomes. In doing so, we are
reflecting on, deliberating about, and ordering ends and means. We can broaden the horizons of such
questioning, and this is what Virtue Ethics in fact typically does, asking: what is the purpose, what are
the goods achieved by, what are the goods necessary as conditions for, what is the end of education?


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      4
What counts as excellence in teaching? What counts as excellence in learning? Asking and attempting
to answer these sorts of questions can open up even bigger and deeper questions, like how – if it does –
does education fit into the framework of living well, of flourishing as a human being?


        I don’t aim to answer precisely these questions here, but to bring them up in order to narrow
some of them into a more specific set. What is the purpose of an SI leader? What are the goods they are
instrumental in producing? What constitutes excellence in their specific type of educational activity?
These sorts of questions, again, all too easily get lost sight of in our actual, busily packed educational
activities, as I know from both my own experience and from observing and speaking with my peers.
We already have curricula set out and built into our courses, we get assigned an SI leader (for which of
course we’re grateful) perhaps even one we recommended, and now it’s a matter of integrating that
student into our course. But, how should we do this?


        A number of varied purposes come to mind when we ask why we have, and how we can use, an
SI leader. The broadest, most overarching one is of course, to improve student learning in our classes,
but what does that mean and how does that take determinate form? At the very least, SI leaders provide
vital contact hours in addition to our own class time and (often little used) office hours, during which
students are engaging with the course material. They may also provide individuated, personal, hands-
on instruction for students who attend their sessions, cover material from different vantage points, or
provide additional examples or applications needed to help students wrap their heads around course
concepts. They support and extend the teaching built into the course, carried out in class sessions,
structured by the instructor. Like course instructors, SI leaders help students progress towards the
goods of knowledge, whether pursued for merely instrumental reasons or towards intrinsic values
residing in subjects, concepts, texts, or approaches studied in the course.


        What is distinctive to SI leaders, as opposed to tutors or TAs are two things: they are all
undergraduate students at that institution, on the same level more or less as the students with whom
they are engaged; and, they are students who excelled in that particular course, with that particular
professor. Both of these provide SI leaders with distinct advantages in reaching and assisting students.
They are regarded as peers of a sort, as living examples that, and how, one can excel in a course, taught
by a particular professor. They are viewed as particularly well-informed not just about a given subject
in general, but about how their assigned professor structures their course, teaches the material, and
evaluates student performance.


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      5
What makes an SI leader excellent? We instructors need to know this not only so that we can
recognize when we are fortunate enough to have excellent SI leaders, but also so that we can steer the SI
leaders we recruit towards the needed forms and dimensions of excellence. One might suppose that the
greater, easier, and more rapid mastery a potential SI leader demonstrates of course material, the more
effective he or she will be, but this is not necessarily so. In some respects, it is far better to employ an SI
leader who, while intelligent, has struggled at some points or in certain manners with the material,
since such a student now teaching possesses an affective and intellectual grasp of the starting condition
of many students, some understanding of what is required to proceed beyond it, and an ability to model
the means and possibility of success to their peers. Ideally, one would want an SI leader to be
continuing in their own education in the subject matter, expanding their expertise, discerning and
working on their weak points, deepening their understanding, developing a wider and better range of
illustrative examples and applications. SI leaders need to be good students, already doing well and also
on an established trajectory towards further improvement, and likewise they need to be developing
teachers. Towards developing excellence in these two roles, and in the particular combination of them,
SI leaders require some degree of development of one intellectual virtue, practical wisdom, and even
more the development of certain moral virtues. This will also require some development and
understanding of these virtues on the part of instructors.


        What are moral virtues? They are habitual dispositions gradually by practice established within
a person’s character or personality. They take the form of typically and characteristically acting,
feeling, and making use of things like property, relationships, pleasures and pains, even one’s time in
good or right ways. The person who is virtuous possesses , intellectually, affectively, or with a
combination of both, right assessments and attitudes towards what is to be done, what goods are at stake
and how they ought to be best ordered, pursued, produced, or preserved. Possession and practice of the
virtues is what enables a person to flourish in determinate ways and quite often to aid others towards
their own flourishing, their own doing well. Since Aristotle’s time, it has been explicitly recognized that
virtues are mean or middle states, in between vicious and deleterious extremes of deficiency and excess
in the matter with which they are concerned.


        A few other things need be said about virtue. It is possible for a person to do virtuous actions
without him or herself being virtuous, i.e. having that virtue well-established in his or her character.
One might act in the way a virtuous person would, as just, or moderate, or honest, or courageous, but
occasionally rather than consistently. One might behave consistently in the way virtuous people tend


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                       6
to, but not because one chooses that for its own sake, as the right or good way to behave or be, for
instance when one behaves courageously in order to earn wealth or some other reward, or when one
behaves justly in order to keep on other people’s good sides or to avoid punishment. One can even
recognize the goodness of a virtue, the needfulness of it for oneself, will to practice it consistently, and
not yet be virtuous, because, as Aristotle noted, for the genuinely virtuous person, such responses have
become “second nature,” easy, pleasurable. The person who is moderate or self-controlled with respect
to bodily pleasures such as eating takes the right amounts, at the right times, in the right ways, and
enjoys doing so. Virtue involves choice, and it also involves understanding or knowledge of what the
right thing to do is in determinate situations, going beyond mere reliance on rules, principles, or
procedures, grasping how best to apply them in the circumstances. So, moral virtues are really sets of
dispositions and skills, having interconnected practical, affective, and intellectual dimensions.


        Which among the many virtues that Virtue Ethicists have progressively identified, analyzed, and
reinterpreteted down through the centuries would be particularly important to think about for SI? As I
thought this through, seven main virtues and one additional virtue-like state come to mind. This is not
an exhaustive list, of course, and is likely to grow as this topic gets more thought and discussion. It is
important to point out that in Virtue Ethics, not every single desirable quality a person might have is in
fact something that can be labeled as a virtue. Genuine virtues are complexes of habitually developed
skills and dispositions, and as such have identifiable and intelligible structures which in determinate
situations lead to their possessors choosing a range of right, good, appropriate, needed actions and
having the associated affective responses. So, a trait like “having a work ethic”, if we do not remain at a
surface level of its name and a general positive reaction to it, and examine it more closely, turns out not
to itself be a virtue, but to denote several features which are components of, or which are particular
instantiations of several virtues. Likewise, “forgiveness”, a popular philosophical topic at present, is not
as some have suggested itself a virtue, but rather is something that flows from a virtue, that of “good
temper” or “mildness”.


        The eight moral traits particularly relevant to SI are Justice, Moderation, Courage, Generosity,
Honesty, Good Temper, Friendliness or Compassion, and Self-Control or Perseverance. Most of these are
easily recognizable from Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics , but in a Neo-Aristotelian framework,
informed by generations of continued moral enquiry in that tradition, and in a contemporary setting
understandably unanticipated by Aristotle or even many of his later commentators, the forms they take
will go beyond what we find in that text or in other classic texts of Virtue Ethics. If we complete these


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      7
moral virtues by adding the closely connected intellectual virtue of phronesis or practical wisdom, we
chart out the broad outlines of a moral dimension developed and embodied in skills and dispositions,
one which in practice intersects with the other such dispositions we tend to focus on much more. We
must do more than merely name or identify the virtues, however. We need to analyze and understand
them, particularly in the form they would take for an SI leader.


        What is justice? At bottom, it is a habitual disposition to give and take rightly, to give to others
what is their due, what they deserve, what one ought to give them, and to take from them or from
common resources one’s fair share. Oftentimes the specific shape of justice can be specified to some
extent by laws, guidelines, contracts, agreements, but these as we all know are only one aspect of justice.
One can do what one has agreed to do, following the letter and subverting the spirit of an agreement.
What we tend to denote by the term “work ethic” is in large part a matter of justice, giving a fair amount
of diligent and competent work for a fair amount of compensation. Justice also involves treating people
fairly in relation to each other, distributing resources in a balanced rather than preferential manner.
So, a just SI leader would apportion their time and energy more or less evenly among the students who
come to them, needing assistance, and would do so recognizing that to be the right thing to do, that
which conduces most towards the flourishing of others.


        Moderation (also called Temperance) as a virtue pertains to the uses we make of and the value
we assign to bodily pleasures. This virtue is less likely to be practiced within the context of SI sessions
when SI leaders meet with and assist students, and much more likely to bear upon the time devoted to
preparation outside of class and sessions. As I think all of us remember from our college educations,
some of the most problematic distractions which end up consuming the time and attention students
need to devote to study tend to be various bodily pleasures, many the exact sorts Aristotle himself wrote
about in his own time: the pleasures of eating, drinking, and having or at least pursuing sex.
Temperance does not mean complete abstention from such pleasures, but enjoying them to the right
degree, at the right time, in the right ways, and for a student as well as for an instructor, this means in
such ways as to not interfere with or even cut into the time and energy needed for focusing on one’s
main tasks. The sorts of pleasures I think are most likely to present problems, and which a temperate SI
leader will enjoy but in moderation, will be other types, like watching television, various internet
activities including social media, and other types of face-to-face socializing.




(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      8
Courage is an interesting, and often misunderstood virtue, and one that is needed in a variety of
ways both for instructors and for students, ways differing greatly from the battlefield paradigms
Aristotle understandably focused on and from the common and typically unreflected-upon tropes of
our own late modern culture, particularly that of education. Courage consists in feeling and acting
with the right amounts of confidence and fear, those appropriate to the object of threat or fear and to
the situation. The development of courage is needed in teaching as it is in any field where one has to get
up in front of people, speak, interact, with an audience at first often entirely unconvinced of the value,
sometimes, even of the truth of what one is teaching. For many SI leaders, this is their first time doing
this sort of authoritative, responsible public speaking, particularly as a practice sustained over an entire
semester. Maintaining classroom discipline, setting and enforcing needed boundaries, resisting
attempts by some students to subvert the educational situation, sticking up for oneself and one’s subject,
these require courage. “Taking risks” being “innovative” may require courage, but often in fact don’t,
particularly in situations where those have become buzz-words, whereas guiding students week by
week on the long march through a course curriculum, as a peer-guide just somewhat more advanced in
grasp of the subject, often does.


        Generosity, or, to use the term more often used in translating Aristotle’s eleutheria, Liberality
was originally conceived in terms of giving and taking of wealth, money, property, and the like.
Another resource which one has to spend on others, however, is time, and the generous person spends
or gives time in a reasonable way that goes beyond what justice demands. In our society, we often speak
of giving 110%, or praise people for giving of their time lavishly, but that sort of indiscriminate giving
might actually be more reflective of one vice opposed to Generosity than expressive of that virtue,
which involves giving to the right people, the right amount, on the right occasions, and – this is very
critical – for the right reasons, with the right ends in mind. If the purpose of the extra time given is to
further education, to aid students who are clearly struggling but also clearly committed to learning, that
aligns with Generosity’s demands. Aristotle actually notes a dynamic involved in poor money
management that will apply equally to time management: if one gives too much, indiscriminately, the
giver will in fact not have enough and find themselves forced to take from somewhere else, introducing
further imbalances.


        Honesty is an important trait, about which we need to make a distinction, since there are several
senses of honesty desirable in an SI leader. Clearly needed is what we might call honesty in the
epistemological sense, saying that things are as they are, not saying they are as they are not, for instance


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      9
telling typically underprepared students who have not looked at the syllabus what precisely their
instructor will be grading them on, not telling students that something will be on a test and therefore
must be studied when one knows that the item will in fact not be on the test. Another sense of honesty
which is somewhat underdeveloped in Aristotle’s work but which later Virtue Ethicists have examined
and discussed is Honesty about oneself in relation to other people, specifically about one’s qualities or
achievements. SI leaders are selected precisely because of certain good qualities they have displayed in
practice, including their academic achievements, intelligence, and the sorts of moral qualities we are in
process of discussing here. One of those traits is having and exhibiting a proper perspective on those
very qualities, avoiding extremes of pridefulness or arrogance on the one hand, or false humility or self-
deprecation on the other. One advantage SI leaders can have in reaching and helping students resides
precisely in their status as peers who are also instructors and to some extent offer an encouraging
model to their fellow students, and this requires a consistent self-assessment, particularly in relation to
one’s mastery of the course material, conveyed to one’s fellow students, honestly admitting what one
does know, what one does not know and needs to study further, or what one knows in part but is still
not entirely confident about.


        Good Temper or Patience is a needed virtue as well. Frustration, annoyance, and anger both on
students’ and on instructors’ parts are common emotional reactions in and out of the classroom, for
understandable reasons, not the least of which is that in the process of education, students are being
challenged, not just spoon-fed or coddled. Failing at tasks or in understanding concepts, and the
attendant negative emotions naturally provoked, are not only a frequent occurrence for students, but
sometimes precisely what is needed in order to eventually make progress. We can add to this that many
topics addressed are controversial and that a typical emotional reaction to views one does not hold or
agree with is anger. Students’ lack of preparedness, attitudes of entitlement or lack of motivation,
rudeness or disrespect, not only arising in class but also in SI sessions, can understandably evoke anger
on the part of SI leaders, instructors, even well-prepared and motivated students in a class. Other
people’s expressions of anger, say for instance that of students, can even arouse anger in those who feel
they are being unfairly targeted. The typical manners in which anger manifests and the ways it alters
the angry person’s assessment of the situation, persons, matters being studied, or discussed can easily
interfere with the processes of education, and are difficult to deal with precisely because anger arises
out of perceptions that one has been or is being wronged, and that one’s reactions are right. Still, there
are situations in which one ought to get angry, even when expression of anger provokes reconsideration
and growth on the part of the one with whom another gets angry. Determining when, how, how much,


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      10
at whom, and for what reasons one ought to be angry, is as Aristotle famously said, a quote with which
Daniel Goleman started his book Emotional intelligence, difficult, and requires cultivation of that virtue.


        Another needed virtue, which Aristotle deals with in terms of Friendship or Friendliness, but
which we might also term Compassion or Benevolence, has to do with our attitude of good-will towards
other people, expressed in the structure of our desires and actions, a habitual, characteristic desire of
good for the other, for the sake of the other person and not for oneself. This is a central feature of
Aristotle’s treatment of friendship. The friendly person exhibits this attitude towards others to the right
degree, in the right ways, towards the right people, not indiscriminately, not in a flattering or
obsequious way, perhaps not in every case displayed immediately. It is displayed in action as well as
attitude. Interestingly, Aristotle also speaks about this quality of good-will, eunomia, in other contexts.
It is, along with good moral character and knowledge or good sense, one of the most important things in
rendering a speaker persuasive to an audience, which senses that the speaker actually does care about
their well-being. He also notes that persuasion is involved in all teaching. What are the goods for the
other with which one would be concerned? In the case of education, of teaching and learning, it is
acquisition of knowledge and understanding. The virtuous SI leader will desire these goods for their
fellow students, and consistently convey and further that desire in action and attitude towards them.


        Self-Control is not itself a virtue in Aristotle’s view, not least because it is not a mean state
between two (or more) vicious extremes. A sort of habitual or dispositional structure or dynamic may
be and typically is involved in Self-Control, but it might be better to think of it not as a virtue per se as a
condition for the development of virtues. One index of this is that the Self-Controlled person, like the
virtuous person, recognizes and does what is right or good, what they recognize the relevant virtue to
require of themselves or of anyone else in that situation, but they have to make themselves act in
accordance with virtue. They have to exercise what we often call will-power, make a choice at times
against their own inclinations or other desires, and while they may feel a sense of satisfaction in brining
themselves to do the good or right thing, even in their own making progress in that area, they don’t feel
the sort of pleasure a virtuous person does in the same action. For instance, a genuinely moderate
person would feel pleasure in taking the right amount of food at meals, while a self-controlled person
would take the right amount, recognizing that to be good for them, but would feel pained at not taking
more (and perhaps also some pain at not being where they would like to be). An SI leader, in order to
be effective, will need Self-Control, which can also be called Perseverance, the condition of sticking to



(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      11
willing what one recognizes correctly as being good or right, appropriate or needed, in order to
progress towards fuller acquisition, more complete assimilation, of the good or goods involved.


        Now we need to think about how SI leaders are to identify, understand, practice, and develop
these various desirable moral qualities. One answer is that they will have to do so the same way as
anybody else does, so how do people in general develop virtues? Both intellectual virtues and moral
virtues are products not only of teaching, of progressively acquiring, building, and synthesizing
knowledge as information, but also through practice, through acting, feeling, choosing in determinate
situations. But in the case of moral virtues, practice plays a much more central, in fact indispensible
role. We become just, Aristotle reminds us, by behaving justly over and over again, until with time and
repetition, it becomes a habitual thread woven into the fabric of our character, the composite outcome
of myriad choices now sedimented and settled into a characteristic way of being. One can read all the
treatises in moral philosophy one likes, all of the praises of virtuous dispositions and people, but unless
one actually chooses and does actions in accordance with virtue, such knowledge will remain
inoperative, even deceptively seducing the person into thinking that because they have some intellectual
grasp of virtue, they possess virtue. A significant dimension of the knowledge of virtue cannot be
communicated in a solely intellectual manner, but must be grasped , acquired, deepened, widened
experientially.


        That said, as educators, we know that if we want students to be able to do something, if we want
them to acquire deep structures of skills and dispositions, we do have to not only provide them with
models and occasions to practice, we actually do have to provide them with instruction. One can and
some people do become virtuous through happy coincidence of a good upbringing requiring them to
practice and develop virtues as habits in a more or less unthinking way. That is rather rare in our
contemporary society and culture, which actually presents its members with contradictory an
oversimplified moral messages, facsimiles and simulacra of virtues, even glorifications of or incentives
towards vice, so what the student will realistically require in order to make progress towards virtue will
be assistance in understanding precisely what virtue is.


        How does all of this play out specifically in the situation of SI leaders? What else is needed for
them to develop or to at least recognize the need for and make reasonable progress towards the virtuous
characters that will not only be a key constituent in their own pursuit of the good life, of flourishing in
their own careers, but also make them effective as SI leaders for their fellow students? There’s a clue in


(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                      12
Aristotle’s dictum that in order to lead well, one must have also learned to follow well, to take direction,
to do what is asked of one, to understand, then meet and then exceed expectations reasonably placed
upon one. In order for this to occur, they must not only have followed well, they must have been led
well, and insofar as they remain students, they must not only continue to follow well, to learn, they must
also continue to be led well, to be taught. And, this falls upon the instructor. An SI leader might well
realize that a certain virtue is important and necessary for good teaching and learning to occur
precisely by observing the effects of its absence in their instructor, a lack of Good Temper for example,
manifesting in berating students when provoked and digressing into tirades about lack of preparation
which do nothing to motivate students towards better preparedness. But, this is unlikely, and merely
learning not to do something tells the learner relatively little about what one ought to do instead, what
that would look like. When it comes down to it, if indeed virtues are needed by SI leaders, instructors
will have to take on the task of instructing them and guiding them, and this in turn will require that
instructors themselves, if not virtuous, be at least on the way to virtue and have an adequately
developed degree of knowledge of what virtue is, what the virtues are, and what the virtues dictate.


Abstract: My presentation will focus on identifying, understanding, and cultivating batches of associated skills
and dispositions desirable and needed if SI leaders are to perform their functions well, and if instructors are to
effectively integrate SI leaders into their courses. These sets of skills and dispositions are termed intellectual and
moral virtues in classical (particularly Aristotelian) Moral Philosophy, upon whose resources I will be drawing to
illuminate topics in my presentation. I will also be drawing on my three year experience of full-time teaching
Core courses and employing SI leaders at Fayetteville State University, which included some successes and also
some failures with SI.


In the course of my presentation, I will introduce the participants to some of the rudiments of classical moral
theory, discuss what intellectual and moral virtues are and how they are cultivated, identify which virtues are
particularly needed by SI leaders and instructors and how they may be thoughtfully cultivated and progressively
built. I will also provide participants with take-away resources to assist them in further study of the matters
discussed.




(Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011)
                                                           13

Contenu connexe

Tendances

Chapter 5 Cognitive, Psychomotor and Affective Domains of Objectives as Basis...
Chapter 5 Cognitive, Psychomotor and Affective Domains of Objectives as Basis...Chapter 5 Cognitive, Psychomotor and Affective Domains of Objectives as Basis...
Chapter 5 Cognitive, Psychomotor and Affective Domains of Objectives as Basis...almera352
 
PUP 4095 Assignment Guidelines
PUP 4095 Assignment GuidelinesPUP 4095 Assignment Guidelines
PUP 4095 Assignment GuidelinesLaura Taylor
 
Critical reflection
Critical reflection Critical reflection
Critical reflection newroz
 
Road to Transformation Part 2: Reflective Practice E Portfolio
Road to Transformation Part 2: Reflective Practice E PortfolioRoad to Transformation Part 2: Reflective Practice E Portfolio
Road to Transformation Part 2: Reflective Practice E Portfoliormg6449
 
Assessment tools for higher learning
Assessment tools for higher learningAssessment tools for higher learning
Assessment tools for higher learningsharifahshahab
 
Reflective Practice E portfolio
Reflective Practice E portfolioReflective Practice E portfolio
Reflective Practice E portfoliormg6449
 
Reflective Piece Final assignment portfolio
Reflective Piece Final assignment  portfolioReflective Piece Final assignment  portfolio
Reflective Piece Final assignment portfoliormg6449
 
Slide 2 analysis of terms in education
Slide 2 analysis  of terms in educationSlide 2 analysis  of terms in education
Slide 2 analysis of terms in educationSee Yuen
 
Assessment in the Affective Domain
Assessment in the Affective DomainAssessment in the Affective Domain
Assessment in the Affective Domainrenielconstantino
 
Assessment in the affective domain
Assessment in the affective domainAssessment in the affective domain
Assessment in the affective domainMilton Pates
 
Assessment in the affective domain
Assessment in the affective domainAssessment in the affective domain
Assessment in the affective domainCyra Mae Soreda
 

Tendances (20)

Chapter 5 Cognitive, Psychomotor and Affective Domains of Objectives as Basis...
Chapter 5 Cognitive, Psychomotor and Affective Domains of Objectives as Basis...Chapter 5 Cognitive, Psychomotor and Affective Domains of Objectives as Basis...
Chapter 5 Cognitive, Psychomotor and Affective Domains of Objectives as Basis...
 
Activity 4
Activity 4Activity 4
Activity 4
 
Bloom's taxonomy of learning domains
Bloom's taxonomy of learning domainsBloom's taxonomy of learning domains
Bloom's taxonomy of learning domains
 
PUP 4095 Assignment Guidelines
PUP 4095 Assignment GuidelinesPUP 4095 Assignment Guidelines
PUP 4095 Assignment Guidelines
 
Critical reflection
Critical reflection Critical reflection
Critical reflection
 
Bloom's Taxonomy
Bloom's TaxonomyBloom's Taxonomy
Bloom's Taxonomy
 
Affective Assessment
Affective AssessmentAffective Assessment
Affective Assessment
 
Road to Transformation Part 2: Reflective Practice E Portfolio
Road to Transformation Part 2: Reflective Practice E PortfolioRoad to Transformation Part 2: Reflective Practice E Portfolio
Road to Transformation Part 2: Reflective Practice E Portfolio
 
Conceptualising authenticeducation
Conceptualising authenticeducationConceptualising authenticeducation
Conceptualising authenticeducation
 
Assessment tools for higher learning
Assessment tools for higher learningAssessment tools for higher learning
Assessment tools for higher learning
 
Reflective Practice E portfolio
Reflective Practice E portfolioReflective Practice E portfolio
Reflective Practice E portfolio
 
Reflective Piece Final assignment portfolio
Reflective Piece Final assignment  portfolioReflective Piece Final assignment  portfolio
Reflective Piece Final assignment portfolio
 
Slide 2 analysis of terms in education
Slide 2 analysis  of terms in educationSlide 2 analysis  of terms in education
Slide 2 analysis of terms in education
 
Assessment in the Affective Domain
Assessment in the Affective DomainAssessment in the Affective Domain
Assessment in the Affective Domain
 
Assessment in the affective domain
Assessment in the affective domainAssessment in the affective domain
Assessment in the affective domain
 
Assessment in the affective domain
Assessment in the affective domainAssessment in the affective domain
Assessment in the affective domain
 
Bloom's taxonomy
Bloom's taxonomyBloom's taxonomy
Bloom's taxonomy
 
Concepts
ConceptsConcepts
Concepts
 
Bloom's Taxonomy
Bloom's Taxonomy Bloom's Taxonomy
Bloom's Taxonomy
 
What is a philosophy
What is a philosophyWhat is a philosophy
What is a philosophy
 

En vedette

The Stickiness of Thought: Exploring Cognitive Science, Pedagogy, and Collegi...
The Stickiness of Thought: Exploring Cognitive Science, Pedagogy, and Collegi...The Stickiness of Thought: Exploring Cognitive Science, Pedagogy, and Collegi...
The Stickiness of Thought: Exploring Cognitive Science, Pedagogy, and Collegi...Lehman Teaching & Learning Commons
 
The Effects of Study Skills Training and Peer Coaching of At-Risk Students on...
The Effects of Study Skills Training and Peer Coaching of At-Risk Students on...The Effects of Study Skills Training and Peer Coaching of At-Risk Students on...
The Effects of Study Skills Training and Peer Coaching of At-Risk Students on...Lehman Teaching & Learning Commons
 
Providing Feedback to Improve Performance
Providing Feedback to Improve PerformanceProviding Feedback to Improve Performance
Providing Feedback to Improve PerformancePooja Ganesh
 
Effective feedback delivery
Effective feedback deliveryEffective feedback delivery
Effective feedback deliveryGaurav bhatnagar
 
10 steps in giving effective Feedback
10 steps in giving effective Feedback10 steps in giving effective Feedback
10 steps in giving effective FeedbackTrainers Advice
 

En vedette (7)

The Stickiness of Thought: Exploring Cognitive Science, Pedagogy, and Collegi...
The Stickiness of Thought: Exploring Cognitive Science, Pedagogy, and Collegi...The Stickiness of Thought: Exploring Cognitive Science, Pedagogy, and Collegi...
The Stickiness of Thought: Exploring Cognitive Science, Pedagogy, and Collegi...
 
Virtue ethics si presentation
Virtue ethics si presentationVirtue ethics si presentation
Virtue ethics si presentation
 
The SI Star: Review Session: Building Blocks
The SI Star: Review Session: Building Blocks The SI Star: Review Session: Building Blocks
The SI Star: Review Session: Building Blocks
 
The Effects of Study Skills Training and Peer Coaching of At-Risk Students on...
The Effects of Study Skills Training and Peer Coaching of At-Risk Students on...The Effects of Study Skills Training and Peer Coaching of At-Risk Students on...
The Effects of Study Skills Training and Peer Coaching of At-Risk Students on...
 
Providing Feedback to Improve Performance
Providing Feedback to Improve PerformanceProviding Feedback to Improve Performance
Providing Feedback to Improve Performance
 
Effective feedback delivery
Effective feedback deliveryEffective feedback delivery
Effective feedback delivery
 
10 steps in giving effective Feedback
10 steps in giving effective Feedback10 steps in giving effective Feedback
10 steps in giving effective Feedback
 

Similaire à Teaching (With) Virtues through Incorporating Supplemental Instruction

Similaire à Teaching (With) Virtues through Incorporating Supplemental Instruction (20)

Creative and critical approaches to teaching students to think ethically: phr...
Creative and critical approaches to teaching students to think ethically: phr...Creative and critical approaches to teaching students to think ethically: phr...
Creative and critical approaches to teaching students to think ethically: phr...
 
T&L Techniques & their MGT.docx
T&L Techniques & their MGT.docxT&L Techniques & their MGT.docx
T&L Techniques & their MGT.docx
 
Critical Reflection Essay
Critical Reflection EssayCritical Reflection Essay
Critical Reflection Essay
 
Teaching Philosophy
Teaching PhilosophyTeaching Philosophy
Teaching Philosophy
 
Business Contextual ethics
Business Contextual ethicsBusiness Contextual ethics
Business Contextual ethics
 
Assignment
AssignmentAssignment
Assignment
 
Psychology & philosophy of education
Psychology & philosophy of educationPsychology & philosophy of education
Psychology & philosophy of education
 
Theories on training and learning
Theories on training and learningTheories on training and learning
Theories on training and learning
 
Reflective Practice
Reflective PracticeReflective Practice
Reflective Practice
 
Module 1_Part A.pdf
Module 1_Part A.pdfModule 1_Part A.pdf
Module 1_Part A.pdf
 
What is reflection
What is reflectionWhat is reflection
What is reflection
 
BradHurstCLP
BradHurstCLPBradHurstCLP
BradHurstCLP
 
Bloom's taxonomy revised
Bloom's taxonomy revisedBloom's taxonomy revised
Bloom's taxonomy revised
 
Transdisciplinary
TransdisciplinaryTransdisciplinary
Transdisciplinary
 
Module 1.pptx
Module 1.pptxModule 1.pptx
Module 1.pptx
 
Aims and Objectives of Teaching Science.pdf
Aims and Objectives of Teaching Science.pdfAims and Objectives of Teaching Science.pdf
Aims and Objectives of Teaching Science.pdf
 
Pedagogy
PedagogyPedagogy
Pedagogy
 
GEB-PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION
GEB-PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATIONGEB-PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION
GEB-PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION
 
Ritchhart (2007) Education Quarterly Australia 1 The.docx
Ritchhart (2007) Education Quarterly Australia   1 The.docxRitchhart (2007) Education Quarterly Australia   1 The.docx
Ritchhart (2007) Education Quarterly Australia 1 The.docx
 
Barriers to-organisational-learning-
Barriers to-organisational-learning-Barriers to-organisational-learning-
Barriers to-organisational-learning-
 

Dernier

Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...EduSkills OECD
 
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdfHoldier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdfagholdier
 
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxUnit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxVishalSingh1417
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfSoniaTolstoy
 
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionmicrowave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionMaksud Ahmed
 
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactAccessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactdawncurless
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13Steve Thomason
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityGeoBlogs
 
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)eniolaolutunde
 
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajansocial pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajanpragatimahajan3
 
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...christianmathematics
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAssociation for Project Management
 
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpin
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpinStudent login on Anyboli platform.helpin
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpinRaunakKeshri1
 
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024Janet Corral
 
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfActivity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfciinovamais
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeThiyagu K
 
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactBeyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactPECB
 
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdfClass 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdfAyushMahapatra5
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Krashi Coaching
 

Dernier (20)

Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
Presentation by Andreas Schleicher Tackling the School Absenteeism Crisis 30 ...
 
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdfHoldier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
Holdier Curriculum Vitae (April 2024).pdf
 
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxUnit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
 
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdfBASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK  LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
BASLIQ CURRENT LOOKBOOK LOOKBOOK(1) (1).pdf
 
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introductionmicrowave assisted reaction. General introduction
microwave assisted reaction. General introduction
 
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impactAccessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
Accessible design: Minimum effort, maximum impact
 
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
The Most Excellent Way | 1 Corinthians 13
 
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activityParis 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
Paris 2024 Olympic Geographies - an activity
 
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
Software Engineering Methodologies (overview)
 
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajansocial pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
social pharmacy d-pharm 1st year by Pragati K. Mahajan
 
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
 
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpin
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpinStudent login on Anyboli platform.helpin
Student login on Anyboli platform.helpin
 
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
General AI for Medical Educators April 2024
 
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfActivity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: Structured Data, Assistants, & RAG"
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
 
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global ImpactBeyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
Beyond the EU: DORA and NIS 2 Directive's Global Impact
 
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdfClass 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
Class 11th Physics NEET formula sheet pdf
 
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
Kisan Call Centre - To harness potential of ICT in Agriculture by answer farm...
 

Teaching (With) Virtues through Incorporating Supplemental Instruction

  • 1. Teaching (With) Virtues Through Incorporating Supplemental Instruction Gregory B. Sadler, ReasonIO greg@reasonio.com What sorts of skills and dispositions do we need to attend to or cultivate in order to render Supplemental Instruction a highly effective pedagogical resource? There are three likely immediate answers to this question, responses which do possess their merits in pointing out important factors for success in implementation of this resource: disciplinary knowledge, pedagogical expertise, and the broad category of “people skills”. I’ll acknowledge the importance of these shortly, but before doing that, I’d like to bring up another type of set of skills and dispositions: the virtues, both intellectual and moral. In the next twenty-five or so minutes, I’ll be sketching out a broadly Aristotelian Virtue Ethics framework within which I suggest Supplemental Instruction might be very profitably located and further thought out. I would like to make clear from the start that I’m not proposing that this Virtue Ethics framework be viewed as a competitor to other good ways of understanding and orienting SI w focus more thematically on other aspects or dimensions of SI. I’d rather it be seen as a useful complementary perspective. Multiple sets of skills and dispositions are needed or desirable for both Instructors and students who are Supplemental Instruction leaders or coaches. Expertise in an academic discipline, in what happens to be the subject matter being studied, is one of these. That almost goes without saying, but it is worth dwelling on this, since one of the prevalent misconceptions of which we so often have to disabuse our students is that learning and expertise is largely a matter of acquiring information, rather than of developing a battery of skills, some general like written communication, critical thinking, and problem solving, others specific to the subject matter but often susceptible of transfer or analogy to other contexts when a level of mastery has been attained. Even deeper than skills, and equally important are dispositions, developed habits, general attitudes, outlooks and approaches, affective orientations and patterns of desire and emotional response. In one of the main fields in which I work, Critical Thinking, that field of performance and expertise has long been identified by one of the most rigorous disciplinary models and self-studies, the APA Delphi Report, as consisting specifically in skills and dispositions. Within classical Aristotelian philosophy of education, such an assemblage of interlocking and scaffolded knowledge, skills, and dispositions well-established in the mind of the learner is termed a hexis or habitus. It becomes as it were a possession rooted in the being of the knower (and doer, actor, producer, (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 1
  • 2. communicator) and is, when developed, one type of intellectual virtue, a state of excellence of the human mind. As all of us know, some of us having been schooled by painful experience, there is an art and an expertise whose product is consistently teaching well. It is different from though does bear affinities with certain types of disciplinary expertise. One can be a great scholar in a particular field, afire with palpable and communicable passion for its objects, and yet teach material one knows inside and out in ways confusing, uninformative, even inscrutable to one’s students. This is a second sort of skills and desirable dispositions susceptible of being taught, even formalized in certain systems to some degree. A third is that set which often get called things like “people skills,” not merely a matter of communication abilities, but the capacity to relate oneself to others, to their ideas, environments, emotions, ideas, experiences. This third set of skills and dispositions in fact overlaps in part with the second, one reason why teaching well cannot be routinized, turned into a science, reduced to lesson plans, etc. – the guardrails of pedagogy. Both sets of skills and dispositions, I should point out, may involve the sort of habitus specific to disciplinary knowledge. It’s worth noting for the moment that they also involve the excellence of phronesis, prudentia, or practical wisdom, which I’ll discuss a bit later. An ideal instructor develops, possesses, exhibits, integrates, and models well all three of these all of the time. Real instructors like ourselves, of course, do these more or less well, more or less consistently, stronger in some areas, at particular times, in certain types of situations than in others, hopefully improving, reflecting on good or bad experiences, intentions, and outcomes, adding to our areas of strength and expertise through theoretical study, interaction with our peers, appropriating useful or engaging resources, putting things into practice, and thoughtful reassessment. As a result – or better put – through these processes, education occurs, learning takes place within, through, by students, more or less successfully. Hopefully the students come out of the class not only having learned disciplinary information at a surface and easily forgotten level, but at the deeper, more retentive and integrated levels signified when we speak of disciplinary knowledge as a habitus. They might have developed some initial or additional competencies in people skills or even in pedagogical competency, depending on what has taken place in the class, what the students themselves have done, participated in, observed, studied, and reflected upon. Adding an SI leader or any sort of intermediary, a Teaching Assistant or a Tutor for instance, renders these matters more complex, since the intermediary functions as an instructor, albeit at a (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 2
  • 3. different level and in different ways, and as a student, albeit a student with a higher, more integrated grasp of the course material. There’s also the question of the degree to, and the ways which the instructor teaches, interacts with, and fosters the development of the SI leader, and the feedback about or insight into the students provided to the instructor by the SI leader who has a unique and useful vantage point from which to observe and interact with students. With this more complex and potentially more productive arrangement outlined, we can raise the question of whether what is going on, what could potentially be going on, what ought to be going on, and what we as instructors would like to be going on – for these are not the same and can often suffer a disconnect -- can be adequately conceptualized solely in terms of disciplinary knowledge, pedagogical expertise, and people skills. All of these are important, to be sure, but I would like to say that, and to some extent say why and how, thinking about SI in terms of the family of approaches in moral theory called Virtue Ethics contributes to developing a yet more adequate understanding of what still more effective use of SI would look like. So, before doing those things, let me make clear some of the suggestions I am and am not making. I am suggesting that Virtue Ethics provides a needed complement to other more explicitly pedagogical-theoretical and less explicitly moral-theoretical approaches. I am not suggesting that Virtue Ethics is a substitute for other approaches. I am also not saying that the instructor whose disciplinary competence lies in some other field now also needs to become a disciplinary expert in Philosophy or Ethics, let alone a specialist in Virtue Ethics. I am saying that some of the typical components of a Virtue Ethics approach are susceptible of being adopted and appropriated as useful portions of one’s own approach to effective employment of SI leaders. These components do this in two ways. There are some ideas or considerations a Virtue Ethics approach provides unlikely to be provided or even realized as needed in its absence. There are other ideas or considerations already in place, on the table, which while making good sense in themselves, find themselves further illuminated by a Virtue Ethics approach, one example of this being practical wisdom ‘s important role in pedagogical expertise and people skills. What I plan to do in this short talk, before opening the floor up to address any questions, concerns, complaints, and then to engage in dialogue, are four things. I’m going to give a necessarily very brief overview of Virtue Ethics as a type of moral theory. Then, I’m going to look at the purposes or ends of SI within that framework. After that, I’m going to discuss which virtues (and vices) are important to focus upon in order to ensure effective use of SI. Lastly, I’m going to talk a bit about (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 3
  • 4. conditions necessary for developing virtues and integrating them with the three other sets of skills and dispositions. So, what is Virtue Ethics? Along with Utilitarianism, Deontological Ethics, Natural Law Ethics, and Ethics of Care, for examples, Virtue Ethics is one of the main well-established and coherent moral theories which we teach in Ethics and various Applied Ethics courses. It actually represents an entire family of moral theories, some of which have been developed in relation or response to each other, so it includes ethics articulated by ancient philosophers such as Plato, Aristotle, and Cicero, medieval thinkers like SS. Augustine, Anselm, Thomas Aquinas, and non-western thinkers like Confucius. It also includes traditions of further interpretation and enquiry continuing these ethics, down to contemporary thinkers like Alasdair MacIntyre and Martha Nussbaum. One of the distinctive features shared by all of these various virtue ethics is making virtues and vices -- the array of good and bad moral dispositions developed as habits over time through actions and choices -- of central consideration in evaluating the goodness or badness, the rightness or wrongness, the appropriateness or inappropriateness of actions, emotional responses , intentions and choices, policies and institutions, even of persons. Instead of simply focusing on conformity to rules discoverable by reason, or following moral or professional codes, or calculating best outcomes for all or most concerned, or displaying compassion, or even on other broad ethical principles, Virtue Ethics goes beyond and situates all of these in relation to three other sets of matters: reframing thinking in terms of horizons of human flourishing, excellence, means and ends; identifying and understanding the specific range of virtues and vices that need to be cultivated or rooted out; and determining how virtues and vices are to actually be cultivated or rooted out in actual practice. It makes good sense to start by stepping back momentarily and asking several questions often overlooked, forgotten, or unsuspected as we go about all our many actions and involvements as educators. Many of us already routinely ask questions similar in intent though different in scope as an integral component of our work as educators. When carrying out integrated course design, for instance, we ask ourselves about broad, big-picture learning goals or objectives for our students as well as determining what student learning outcomes we want to focus on, and then we think about what learning activities would provide practice and ways of assessing those outcomes. In doing so, we are reflecting on, deliberating about, and ordering ends and means. We can broaden the horizons of such questioning, and this is what Virtue Ethics in fact typically does, asking: what is the purpose, what are the goods achieved by, what are the goods necessary as conditions for, what is the end of education? (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 4
  • 5. What counts as excellence in teaching? What counts as excellence in learning? Asking and attempting to answer these sorts of questions can open up even bigger and deeper questions, like how – if it does – does education fit into the framework of living well, of flourishing as a human being? I don’t aim to answer precisely these questions here, but to bring them up in order to narrow some of them into a more specific set. What is the purpose of an SI leader? What are the goods they are instrumental in producing? What constitutes excellence in their specific type of educational activity? These sorts of questions, again, all too easily get lost sight of in our actual, busily packed educational activities, as I know from both my own experience and from observing and speaking with my peers. We already have curricula set out and built into our courses, we get assigned an SI leader (for which of course we’re grateful) perhaps even one we recommended, and now it’s a matter of integrating that student into our course. But, how should we do this? A number of varied purposes come to mind when we ask why we have, and how we can use, an SI leader. The broadest, most overarching one is of course, to improve student learning in our classes, but what does that mean and how does that take determinate form? At the very least, SI leaders provide vital contact hours in addition to our own class time and (often little used) office hours, during which students are engaging with the course material. They may also provide individuated, personal, hands- on instruction for students who attend their sessions, cover material from different vantage points, or provide additional examples or applications needed to help students wrap their heads around course concepts. They support and extend the teaching built into the course, carried out in class sessions, structured by the instructor. Like course instructors, SI leaders help students progress towards the goods of knowledge, whether pursued for merely instrumental reasons or towards intrinsic values residing in subjects, concepts, texts, or approaches studied in the course. What is distinctive to SI leaders, as opposed to tutors or TAs are two things: they are all undergraduate students at that institution, on the same level more or less as the students with whom they are engaged; and, they are students who excelled in that particular course, with that particular professor. Both of these provide SI leaders with distinct advantages in reaching and assisting students. They are regarded as peers of a sort, as living examples that, and how, one can excel in a course, taught by a particular professor. They are viewed as particularly well-informed not just about a given subject in general, but about how their assigned professor structures their course, teaches the material, and evaluates student performance. (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 5
  • 6. What makes an SI leader excellent? We instructors need to know this not only so that we can recognize when we are fortunate enough to have excellent SI leaders, but also so that we can steer the SI leaders we recruit towards the needed forms and dimensions of excellence. One might suppose that the greater, easier, and more rapid mastery a potential SI leader demonstrates of course material, the more effective he or she will be, but this is not necessarily so. In some respects, it is far better to employ an SI leader who, while intelligent, has struggled at some points or in certain manners with the material, since such a student now teaching possesses an affective and intellectual grasp of the starting condition of many students, some understanding of what is required to proceed beyond it, and an ability to model the means and possibility of success to their peers. Ideally, one would want an SI leader to be continuing in their own education in the subject matter, expanding their expertise, discerning and working on their weak points, deepening their understanding, developing a wider and better range of illustrative examples and applications. SI leaders need to be good students, already doing well and also on an established trajectory towards further improvement, and likewise they need to be developing teachers. Towards developing excellence in these two roles, and in the particular combination of them, SI leaders require some degree of development of one intellectual virtue, practical wisdom, and even more the development of certain moral virtues. This will also require some development and understanding of these virtues on the part of instructors. What are moral virtues? They are habitual dispositions gradually by practice established within a person’s character or personality. They take the form of typically and characteristically acting, feeling, and making use of things like property, relationships, pleasures and pains, even one’s time in good or right ways. The person who is virtuous possesses , intellectually, affectively, or with a combination of both, right assessments and attitudes towards what is to be done, what goods are at stake and how they ought to be best ordered, pursued, produced, or preserved. Possession and practice of the virtues is what enables a person to flourish in determinate ways and quite often to aid others towards their own flourishing, their own doing well. Since Aristotle’s time, it has been explicitly recognized that virtues are mean or middle states, in between vicious and deleterious extremes of deficiency and excess in the matter with which they are concerned. A few other things need be said about virtue. It is possible for a person to do virtuous actions without him or herself being virtuous, i.e. having that virtue well-established in his or her character. One might act in the way a virtuous person would, as just, or moderate, or honest, or courageous, but occasionally rather than consistently. One might behave consistently in the way virtuous people tend (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 6
  • 7. to, but not because one chooses that for its own sake, as the right or good way to behave or be, for instance when one behaves courageously in order to earn wealth or some other reward, or when one behaves justly in order to keep on other people’s good sides or to avoid punishment. One can even recognize the goodness of a virtue, the needfulness of it for oneself, will to practice it consistently, and not yet be virtuous, because, as Aristotle noted, for the genuinely virtuous person, such responses have become “second nature,” easy, pleasurable. The person who is moderate or self-controlled with respect to bodily pleasures such as eating takes the right amounts, at the right times, in the right ways, and enjoys doing so. Virtue involves choice, and it also involves understanding or knowledge of what the right thing to do is in determinate situations, going beyond mere reliance on rules, principles, or procedures, grasping how best to apply them in the circumstances. So, moral virtues are really sets of dispositions and skills, having interconnected practical, affective, and intellectual dimensions. Which among the many virtues that Virtue Ethicists have progressively identified, analyzed, and reinterpreteted down through the centuries would be particularly important to think about for SI? As I thought this through, seven main virtues and one additional virtue-like state come to mind. This is not an exhaustive list, of course, and is likely to grow as this topic gets more thought and discussion. It is important to point out that in Virtue Ethics, not every single desirable quality a person might have is in fact something that can be labeled as a virtue. Genuine virtues are complexes of habitually developed skills and dispositions, and as such have identifiable and intelligible structures which in determinate situations lead to their possessors choosing a range of right, good, appropriate, needed actions and having the associated affective responses. So, a trait like “having a work ethic”, if we do not remain at a surface level of its name and a general positive reaction to it, and examine it more closely, turns out not to itself be a virtue, but to denote several features which are components of, or which are particular instantiations of several virtues. Likewise, “forgiveness”, a popular philosophical topic at present, is not as some have suggested itself a virtue, but rather is something that flows from a virtue, that of “good temper” or “mildness”. The eight moral traits particularly relevant to SI are Justice, Moderation, Courage, Generosity, Honesty, Good Temper, Friendliness or Compassion, and Self-Control or Perseverance. Most of these are easily recognizable from Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics , but in a Neo-Aristotelian framework, informed by generations of continued moral enquiry in that tradition, and in a contemporary setting understandably unanticipated by Aristotle or even many of his later commentators, the forms they take will go beyond what we find in that text or in other classic texts of Virtue Ethics. If we complete these (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 7
  • 8. moral virtues by adding the closely connected intellectual virtue of phronesis or practical wisdom, we chart out the broad outlines of a moral dimension developed and embodied in skills and dispositions, one which in practice intersects with the other such dispositions we tend to focus on much more. We must do more than merely name or identify the virtues, however. We need to analyze and understand them, particularly in the form they would take for an SI leader. What is justice? At bottom, it is a habitual disposition to give and take rightly, to give to others what is their due, what they deserve, what one ought to give them, and to take from them or from common resources one’s fair share. Oftentimes the specific shape of justice can be specified to some extent by laws, guidelines, contracts, agreements, but these as we all know are only one aspect of justice. One can do what one has agreed to do, following the letter and subverting the spirit of an agreement. What we tend to denote by the term “work ethic” is in large part a matter of justice, giving a fair amount of diligent and competent work for a fair amount of compensation. Justice also involves treating people fairly in relation to each other, distributing resources in a balanced rather than preferential manner. So, a just SI leader would apportion their time and energy more or less evenly among the students who come to them, needing assistance, and would do so recognizing that to be the right thing to do, that which conduces most towards the flourishing of others. Moderation (also called Temperance) as a virtue pertains to the uses we make of and the value we assign to bodily pleasures. This virtue is less likely to be practiced within the context of SI sessions when SI leaders meet with and assist students, and much more likely to bear upon the time devoted to preparation outside of class and sessions. As I think all of us remember from our college educations, some of the most problematic distractions which end up consuming the time and attention students need to devote to study tend to be various bodily pleasures, many the exact sorts Aristotle himself wrote about in his own time: the pleasures of eating, drinking, and having or at least pursuing sex. Temperance does not mean complete abstention from such pleasures, but enjoying them to the right degree, at the right time, in the right ways, and for a student as well as for an instructor, this means in such ways as to not interfere with or even cut into the time and energy needed for focusing on one’s main tasks. The sorts of pleasures I think are most likely to present problems, and which a temperate SI leader will enjoy but in moderation, will be other types, like watching television, various internet activities including social media, and other types of face-to-face socializing. (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 8
  • 9. Courage is an interesting, and often misunderstood virtue, and one that is needed in a variety of ways both for instructors and for students, ways differing greatly from the battlefield paradigms Aristotle understandably focused on and from the common and typically unreflected-upon tropes of our own late modern culture, particularly that of education. Courage consists in feeling and acting with the right amounts of confidence and fear, those appropriate to the object of threat or fear and to the situation. The development of courage is needed in teaching as it is in any field where one has to get up in front of people, speak, interact, with an audience at first often entirely unconvinced of the value, sometimes, even of the truth of what one is teaching. For many SI leaders, this is their first time doing this sort of authoritative, responsible public speaking, particularly as a practice sustained over an entire semester. Maintaining classroom discipline, setting and enforcing needed boundaries, resisting attempts by some students to subvert the educational situation, sticking up for oneself and one’s subject, these require courage. “Taking risks” being “innovative” may require courage, but often in fact don’t, particularly in situations where those have become buzz-words, whereas guiding students week by week on the long march through a course curriculum, as a peer-guide just somewhat more advanced in grasp of the subject, often does. Generosity, or, to use the term more often used in translating Aristotle’s eleutheria, Liberality was originally conceived in terms of giving and taking of wealth, money, property, and the like. Another resource which one has to spend on others, however, is time, and the generous person spends or gives time in a reasonable way that goes beyond what justice demands. In our society, we often speak of giving 110%, or praise people for giving of their time lavishly, but that sort of indiscriminate giving might actually be more reflective of one vice opposed to Generosity than expressive of that virtue, which involves giving to the right people, the right amount, on the right occasions, and – this is very critical – for the right reasons, with the right ends in mind. If the purpose of the extra time given is to further education, to aid students who are clearly struggling but also clearly committed to learning, that aligns with Generosity’s demands. Aristotle actually notes a dynamic involved in poor money management that will apply equally to time management: if one gives too much, indiscriminately, the giver will in fact not have enough and find themselves forced to take from somewhere else, introducing further imbalances. Honesty is an important trait, about which we need to make a distinction, since there are several senses of honesty desirable in an SI leader. Clearly needed is what we might call honesty in the epistemological sense, saying that things are as they are, not saying they are as they are not, for instance (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 9
  • 10. telling typically underprepared students who have not looked at the syllabus what precisely their instructor will be grading them on, not telling students that something will be on a test and therefore must be studied when one knows that the item will in fact not be on the test. Another sense of honesty which is somewhat underdeveloped in Aristotle’s work but which later Virtue Ethicists have examined and discussed is Honesty about oneself in relation to other people, specifically about one’s qualities or achievements. SI leaders are selected precisely because of certain good qualities they have displayed in practice, including their academic achievements, intelligence, and the sorts of moral qualities we are in process of discussing here. One of those traits is having and exhibiting a proper perspective on those very qualities, avoiding extremes of pridefulness or arrogance on the one hand, or false humility or self- deprecation on the other. One advantage SI leaders can have in reaching and helping students resides precisely in their status as peers who are also instructors and to some extent offer an encouraging model to their fellow students, and this requires a consistent self-assessment, particularly in relation to one’s mastery of the course material, conveyed to one’s fellow students, honestly admitting what one does know, what one does not know and needs to study further, or what one knows in part but is still not entirely confident about. Good Temper or Patience is a needed virtue as well. Frustration, annoyance, and anger both on students’ and on instructors’ parts are common emotional reactions in and out of the classroom, for understandable reasons, not the least of which is that in the process of education, students are being challenged, not just spoon-fed or coddled. Failing at tasks or in understanding concepts, and the attendant negative emotions naturally provoked, are not only a frequent occurrence for students, but sometimes precisely what is needed in order to eventually make progress. We can add to this that many topics addressed are controversial and that a typical emotional reaction to views one does not hold or agree with is anger. Students’ lack of preparedness, attitudes of entitlement or lack of motivation, rudeness or disrespect, not only arising in class but also in SI sessions, can understandably evoke anger on the part of SI leaders, instructors, even well-prepared and motivated students in a class. Other people’s expressions of anger, say for instance that of students, can even arouse anger in those who feel they are being unfairly targeted. The typical manners in which anger manifests and the ways it alters the angry person’s assessment of the situation, persons, matters being studied, or discussed can easily interfere with the processes of education, and are difficult to deal with precisely because anger arises out of perceptions that one has been or is being wronged, and that one’s reactions are right. Still, there are situations in which one ought to get angry, even when expression of anger provokes reconsideration and growth on the part of the one with whom another gets angry. Determining when, how, how much, (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 10
  • 11. at whom, and for what reasons one ought to be angry, is as Aristotle famously said, a quote with which Daniel Goleman started his book Emotional intelligence, difficult, and requires cultivation of that virtue. Another needed virtue, which Aristotle deals with in terms of Friendship or Friendliness, but which we might also term Compassion or Benevolence, has to do with our attitude of good-will towards other people, expressed in the structure of our desires and actions, a habitual, characteristic desire of good for the other, for the sake of the other person and not for oneself. This is a central feature of Aristotle’s treatment of friendship. The friendly person exhibits this attitude towards others to the right degree, in the right ways, towards the right people, not indiscriminately, not in a flattering or obsequious way, perhaps not in every case displayed immediately. It is displayed in action as well as attitude. Interestingly, Aristotle also speaks about this quality of good-will, eunomia, in other contexts. It is, along with good moral character and knowledge or good sense, one of the most important things in rendering a speaker persuasive to an audience, which senses that the speaker actually does care about their well-being. He also notes that persuasion is involved in all teaching. What are the goods for the other with which one would be concerned? In the case of education, of teaching and learning, it is acquisition of knowledge and understanding. The virtuous SI leader will desire these goods for their fellow students, and consistently convey and further that desire in action and attitude towards them. Self-Control is not itself a virtue in Aristotle’s view, not least because it is not a mean state between two (or more) vicious extremes. A sort of habitual or dispositional structure or dynamic may be and typically is involved in Self-Control, but it might be better to think of it not as a virtue per se as a condition for the development of virtues. One index of this is that the Self-Controlled person, like the virtuous person, recognizes and does what is right or good, what they recognize the relevant virtue to require of themselves or of anyone else in that situation, but they have to make themselves act in accordance with virtue. They have to exercise what we often call will-power, make a choice at times against their own inclinations or other desires, and while they may feel a sense of satisfaction in brining themselves to do the good or right thing, even in their own making progress in that area, they don’t feel the sort of pleasure a virtuous person does in the same action. For instance, a genuinely moderate person would feel pleasure in taking the right amount of food at meals, while a self-controlled person would take the right amount, recognizing that to be good for them, but would feel pained at not taking more (and perhaps also some pain at not being where they would like to be). An SI leader, in order to be effective, will need Self-Control, which can also be called Perseverance, the condition of sticking to (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 11
  • 12. willing what one recognizes correctly as being good or right, appropriate or needed, in order to progress towards fuller acquisition, more complete assimilation, of the good or goods involved. Now we need to think about how SI leaders are to identify, understand, practice, and develop these various desirable moral qualities. One answer is that they will have to do so the same way as anybody else does, so how do people in general develop virtues? Both intellectual virtues and moral virtues are products not only of teaching, of progressively acquiring, building, and synthesizing knowledge as information, but also through practice, through acting, feeling, choosing in determinate situations. But in the case of moral virtues, practice plays a much more central, in fact indispensible role. We become just, Aristotle reminds us, by behaving justly over and over again, until with time and repetition, it becomes a habitual thread woven into the fabric of our character, the composite outcome of myriad choices now sedimented and settled into a characteristic way of being. One can read all the treatises in moral philosophy one likes, all of the praises of virtuous dispositions and people, but unless one actually chooses and does actions in accordance with virtue, such knowledge will remain inoperative, even deceptively seducing the person into thinking that because they have some intellectual grasp of virtue, they possess virtue. A significant dimension of the knowledge of virtue cannot be communicated in a solely intellectual manner, but must be grasped , acquired, deepened, widened experientially. That said, as educators, we know that if we want students to be able to do something, if we want them to acquire deep structures of skills and dispositions, we do have to not only provide them with models and occasions to practice, we actually do have to provide them with instruction. One can and some people do become virtuous through happy coincidence of a good upbringing requiring them to practice and develop virtues as habits in a more or less unthinking way. That is rather rare in our contemporary society and culture, which actually presents its members with contradictory an oversimplified moral messages, facsimiles and simulacra of virtues, even glorifications of or incentives towards vice, so what the student will realistically require in order to make progress towards virtue will be assistance in understanding precisely what virtue is. How does all of this play out specifically in the situation of SI leaders? What else is needed for them to develop or to at least recognize the need for and make reasonable progress towards the virtuous characters that will not only be a key constituent in their own pursuit of the good life, of flourishing in their own careers, but also make them effective as SI leaders for their fellow students? There’s a clue in (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 12
  • 13. Aristotle’s dictum that in order to lead well, one must have also learned to follow well, to take direction, to do what is asked of one, to understand, then meet and then exceed expectations reasonably placed upon one. In order for this to occur, they must not only have followed well, they must have been led well, and insofar as they remain students, they must not only continue to follow well, to learn, they must also continue to be led well, to be taught. And, this falls upon the instructor. An SI leader might well realize that a certain virtue is important and necessary for good teaching and learning to occur precisely by observing the effects of its absence in their instructor, a lack of Good Temper for example, manifesting in berating students when provoked and digressing into tirades about lack of preparation which do nothing to motivate students towards better preparedness. But, this is unlikely, and merely learning not to do something tells the learner relatively little about what one ought to do instead, what that would look like. When it comes down to it, if indeed virtues are needed by SI leaders, instructors will have to take on the task of instructing them and guiding them, and this in turn will require that instructors themselves, if not virtuous, be at least on the way to virtue and have an adequately developed degree of knowledge of what virtue is, what the virtues are, and what the virtues dictate. Abstract: My presentation will focus on identifying, understanding, and cultivating batches of associated skills and dispositions desirable and needed if SI leaders are to perform their functions well, and if instructors are to effectively integrate SI leaders into their courses. These sets of skills and dispositions are termed intellectual and moral virtues in classical (particularly Aristotelian) Moral Philosophy, upon whose resources I will be drawing to illuminate topics in my presentation. I will also be drawing on my three year experience of full-time teaching Core courses and employing SI leaders at Fayetteville State University, which included some successes and also some failures with SI. In the course of my presentation, I will introduce the participants to some of the rudiments of classical moral theory, discuss what intellectual and moral virtues are and how they are cultivated, identify which virtues are particularly needed by SI leaders and instructors and how they may be thoughtfully cultivated and progressively built. I will also provide participants with take-away resources to assist them in further study of the matters discussed. (Draft: not to be quoted from or reproduced without permission of author. Copyright Gregory B. Sadler, 2011) 13