SlideShare une entreprise Scribd logo
1  sur  23
Télécharger pour lire hors ligne
The Neural Correlates of Consciousness
                                                               An Update
                                            GIULIO TONONIa             AND   CHRISTOF KOCHb
                   a
                       Department of Psychiatry, University of Wisconsin, Madison, Wisconsin, USA
              b
                  Division of Biology and the Division of Engineering and Applied Science, California
                                  Institute of Technology, Pasadena, California, USA


          This review examines recent advances in the study of brain correlates of consciousness. First, we
          briefly discuss some useful distinctions between consciousness and other brain functions. We then
          examine what has been learned by studying global changes in the level of consciousness, such as
          sleep, anesthesia, and seizures. Next we consider some of the most common paradigms used to
          study the neural correlates for specific conscious percepts and examine what recent findings say
          about the role of different brain regions in giving rise to consciousness for that percept. Then we
          discuss dynamic aspects of neural activity, such as sustained versus phasic activity, feedforward
          versus reentrant activity, and the role of neural synchronization. Finally, we briefly consider how
          a theoretical analysis of the fundamental properties of consciousness can usefully complement
          neurobiological studies.

          Key words: consciousness; brain; information



                          Introduction                                      consciousness is, how it can be generated by a physi-
                                                                            cal system, and how it can be measured and then to
   There are several strategies by which scientists can                     test the predictions of the theory against data from
approach the relationship between the brain and con-                        neuroscience (Tononi 2004b).
sciousness. One is to wait and hope that, once we know                         This review focuses on recent advances in the study
all there is to know about neuroanatomy and neuro-                          of the NCC. First, we briefly discuss some useful dis-
physiology (or maybe when we can model in detail the                        tinctions between consciousness and other brain func-
working of the entire brain; Markram 2006), the an-                         tions. We then examine what has been learned about
swer will somehow pop out. A more practical approach                        the NCC by studying global changes in the level of con-
is to use the tools of neuroscience that are available                      sciousness, such as sleep, anesthesia, and generalized
now to shed light on the neural structures and activ-                       seizures. Next, we consider some of the most com-
ity patterns that underlie consciousness. For example,                      mon paradigms used to study the NCC for specific
one can examine how brain activity changes when,                            conscious percepts and examine what recent findings
everything else being as equal as possible, a stimulus                      say about the role of different brain regions in giving
is experienced or not. In this way, one can attempt to                      rise to consciousness for that percept. Finally, we dis-
identify, more and more precisely, the neural correlates                    cuss the relation to the NCC of dynamic aspects of
of consciousness (NCC), defined as the minimal neuronal                      neural activity, such as sustained versus phasic activity,
mechanisms jointly sufficient for any one specific conscious percept          feedforward versus reentrant activity, and the role of
(Koch 2003). A complementary strategy is to consider                        neural synchronization. We end with a few remarks on
conditions in which consciousness is globally dimin-                        the importance of a combined theoretical and neuro-
ished, such as deep sleep or anesthesia, and ask what                       biological approach.
has changed in the brain. Finally, another approach is
to develop a theoretical framework that clarifies what
                                                                                 Consciousness and Other Brain
                                                                                           Functions
   Address for correspondence: Christof Koch, Division of Biology and the
Division of Engineering and Applied Science, 216-76, California Institute
                                                                               Many suggestions have been ventured in the hope of
of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125. Fax: +1-626-796-8876.                    alleviating the puzzle of subjective experience. Perhaps
   koch@klab.caltech.edu                                                    consciousness emerges somehow when an organism is
   Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 1124: 239–261 (2008).                 C   2008 New York Academy of Sciences.
   doi: 10.1196/annals.1440.004                                         239
240                                                                       Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

immersed in some complex sensorimotor loop that in-            et al. 1998). Patients with the locked-in syndrome can
cludes the environment. Another common idea is that            be almost completely paralyzed, and yet they are just
consciousness may somehow arise when one part of               as conscious as healthy subjects (Laureys et al. 2005)
the brain, acting as the “subject” (typically the front),      and can compose eloquent accounts of their condition
looks upon another part as its “object” (typically the         (Bauby 1997). A transient form of paralysis is one of the
back), and evaluates or reflects upon its activity. It is of-   characteristic features of narcolepsy. Severe cataleptic
ten thought that in the end consciousness may reduce           attacks can last for minutes and leave the patient col-
to attention and its brain mechanisms, since we are            lapsed on the floor, utterly unable to move or to sig-
usually conscious of what we attend. Much could be             nal, but fully aware of her surroundings (Guilleminault
said about each of these suggestions. Here, we briefly          1976; Siegel 2000). Or consider the Californian drug
consider some recent results (and some very old evi-           addicts known as the frozen addicts who acquired some of
dence) indicating that consciousness—in the sense of           the symptoms of severe, late-stage Parkinson’s disease,
having an experience—does not require sensorimotor             fully conscious, yet unable to move or speak (Langston
loops involving the body and the world, does not re-           & Palfreman 1995). All six had previously taken syn-
quire self-reflection (or language), and does not reduce        thetic heroin tainted with MPTP, which selectively and
to attention.                                                  permanently destroyed dopamine-producing neurons
                                                               in their basal ganglia. Thus, consciousness here and
   Consciousness and Sensory Input/Motor                       now seems to depend on what certain parts of the brain
                  Output                                       are doing, without requiring any obligatory interaction
    We are usually conscious of what goes on around            with the environment or the body.
us, and occasionally of what goes on within our body.
So it is only natural to think that consciousness may                 Consciousness and Self-Reflection
be tightly linked to the ongoing interaction we main-             Consciousness is usually evaluated by verbal reports,
tain with the world and the body. However, there are           and questions about consciousness (“Did you see any-
many examples to the contrary. We are conscious of             thing on the screen?”) are answered by “looking in-
our thoughts, which do not seem to correspond to any-          side” retrospectively and reporting what one has just
thing out there; we can also imagine things that are           experienced. So it is perhaps natural to suggest that
not out there. When we do so, sensory areas can be             consciousness may arise through the ability to reflect
activated from the inside (Kosslyn et al. 2001), though        on our own perceptions: our brain would form a scene
there are some differences (Amedi et al. 2005). Also,          of what it sees, but we would become conscious of it—
stimulus-independent consciousness is associated with          experience it subjectively—only when we, as a subject
its own patterns of activation within cortex and tha-          of experience, watch that scene from the inside. This
lamus (Mason et al. 2007). During dreams, we are               suggestion is often framed in a neurobiological context
virtually disconnected from the environment (Hobson            by assuming that patterns of activity corresponding
et al. 2000)—hardly anything of what happens around            to “unconscious” or “subconscious” percepts form in
us enters consciousness, and our muscles are paralyzed         posterior regions of the cerebral cortex involved in the
(except for eye muscles and diaphragm). Nevertheless,          categorization/association of sensory stimuli. These
we are vividly conscious: all that seems to matter is          percepts then become conscious when mainly ante-
that the thalamocortical system continues to function          rior prefrontal and cingulate regions involved in self-
more or less as in wakefulness, as shown by unit record-       representations interact with posterior cortex, perhaps
ing, EEG, and neuroimaging studies performed dur-              by reading in signals through forward connections and
ing rapid eye movement (REM) sleep, when dreams                selectively amplifying them through back connections
are most intense (Maquet et al. 1996). Interestingly,          (more on this later).
certain regions of the thalamocortical systems, such              There is of course no doubt that the brain catego-
as dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, are deactivated in          rizes its own patterns of activity in the sense that neu-
REM sleep, which likely accounts for some peculiari-           rons respond mainly to the activity of other neurons,
ties of dreaming experiences, such as the reduction of         so the brain is constantly “looking at itself.” However,
voluntary control.                                             this is not necessarily in terms of a “subject” (the front)
    Neurological evidence also indicates that neither          looking at an “object” represented in sensory cortices
sensory inputs nor motor outputs are needed to gener-          (the back). Leaving aside the mystery of why reflecting
ate consciousness. For instance, retinally blind people        on something should make it conscious, this scenario
can both imagine and dream visually if they become             is made less plausible by a common observation: when
blind after 6–7 years of age or so (Hollins 1985; Buchel       we become absorbed in some intense perceptual task,
Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness                                                         241


for example watching an engrossing movie, playing a         and social setting. Although displaying many of the
fast-paced video game, or rushing through the woods         typical frontal lobe behavioral disturbances, he never
at high speed, we are vividly conscious—we are im-          complained of loss of sensory perception, nor did he
mersed in the rapid flow of experience—without any           show visual or other deficits (Mataro et al. 2001). An-
need for reflection or introspection. Often, we become       other case is that of a 27-year-old woman with mas-
so immersed in such flow that we may lose the sense          sive bilateral prefrontal damage of unclear etiology
of self, the inner voice. Perhaps the habit of thinking     (Markowitsch & Kessler 2000). While manifesting
about consciousness has distracted the scholars who         grossly deficient scores in frontal lobe sensitive tests,
write upon such matters to devalue the unreflective          she showed no abnormal perceptual abilities (that is
nature of much of experience.                               not to say that such patients do not suffer from subtle
    A recent neuroimaging study by Malach and col-          visual deficits; Barcelo et al. 2000).
laborators (Hasson et al. 2004) throws some inter-
esting light on these old observations. Subjects were                 Consciousness and Attention
scanned with fMRI in three conditions. In the slow             Consciousness and attention have resisted clear and
categorization task, subjects were asked to catego-         compelling definitions. Few would dispute that the re-
rize pictures into animal/no-animal categories. Dur-        lationship between the two is an intimate one. When
ing the introspective task, subjects viewed the images      subjects pay attention to an object, they become con-
and then introspected about their emotional response        scious of its various attributes; when the focus of at-
(strong/neutral). Finally, the fast categorization task     tention shifts away, the object fades from conscious-
was identical to the “slow” condition but at triple         ness. Indeed, more than a century of research efforts
the stimulation rate. Thus, “slow” and “introspection”      have quantified the ample benefits accrued to attended
conditions were identical in terms of sensory stimuli       and consciously perceived events (Pashler 1998; Braun
and motor output but differed in the cognitive task.        et al. 2001). This has prompted many to posit that the
On the other hand, “slow” and “rapid” conditions            two processes are inextricably interwoven, if not iden-
were similar in the cognitive task but differed in the      tical (Posner 1994; Merikle & Joordens 1997; Chun &
sensorimotor processing and attentional loads. Behav-       Wolfe 2000; O’Regan & Noe 2000). Others, however,
ioral measurements confirmed that self-awareness was         going back to the 19th century, have argued that atten-
high during the introspection task, and virtually abol-     tion and consciousness are distinct phenomena, with
ished during rapid categorization. The neuroimaging         distinct functions and neuronal mechanisms (Iwasaki
results were clear: during introspection there was an       1993; Hardcastle 1997; Lamme 2003; Baars 2005;
activation of prefrontal regions, whereas sensory cor-      Block 2005; Dehaene et al. 2006; Koch & Tsuchiya
tex was strongly activated during rapid categorization.     2007). Recent psychophysical and neurophysiological
Crucially, during introspection self-related cortex was     evidence argues in favor of a dissociation between selec-
deactivated below the rest condition. This deactiva-        tive attention and consciousness, suggesting that events
tion of prefrontal regions was thus the neural corre-       or objects can be attended to without being consciously
late of “losing oneself ” in the task. To the extent that   perceived. Conversely, an event or object can be con-
these prefrontal regions were indeed involved in self-      sciously perceived in the near absence of top-down
representation, these findings suggest that their activa-    attentional processing.
tion is not necessary for the emergence of perceptual
consciousness, but only to reflect upon it and report it     Attention without Consciousness
to others. Indeed, it appears that self-related activity       Consider that subjects can attend to a location for
is actually shut off during highly demanding sensory        many seconds and yet fail to see one or more attributes
tasks.                                                      of an object at that location. In lateral masking (visual
    Lesion studies also seem to support the notion that     crowding), the orientation of a peripherally presented
consciousness does not require prefrontal cortex and,       grating is hidden from conscious sight but remains
by inference, the functions it performs. Though pa-         sufficiently potent to induce an orientation-dependent
tients with widespread, bilateral damage to prefrontal      aftereffect (He et al. 1996) Montaser-Kouhsari and
cortex are rare, two recent clinical studies provide        Rajimehr (2004) showed that an aftereffect induced
some intriguing evidence. A man who, at the age             by an invisible illusory contour required focal atten-
of 21, had fallen on an iron spike that completely          tion, even though the object at the center of attention
penetrated through both of his frontal lobes, never-        was invisible. Naccache and colleagues (2002) elicited
theless went on to live a stable life—marrying and          priming for invisible words (suppressed by a combi-
raising two children—in an appropriate professional         nation of forward and backward masking) but only if
242                                                                      Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

the subject was attending to the invisible prime-target       (or a vehicle), while being unable to distinguish a red-
pair; without attention, the same word failed to elicit       green bisected disk from a green-red one (Li et al.
priming. That is, the subject needs to attend to the          2002). Likewise, subjects can tell male from female
masked stimulus for priming to occur, but the actual          faces or even distinguish a famous from a nonfamous
stimulus is not seen (with an associated d = 0). In           face (Reddy et al. 2004; Reddy & Koch 2006) but are
another experiment, male/female nudes attracted at-           frustrated by tasks that are computationally much sim-
tention and induced involuntary eye movements when            pler (e.g., discriminating a rotated letter “L” from a
they were rendered completely invisible by continuous         rotated “T”). This is quite remarkable. Thus, while we
flash suppression (Jiang et al. 2006). When subjects had       cannot be sure that observers do not deploy some lim-
to discriminate the location of the masked nude from          ited amount of top-down attention in these dual-task
the location of a masked shuffled nude, they were at           experiments that require training and concentration
chance; without the intraocular masking, the images           (i.e., high arousal), it remains true that subjects can
are clearly visible. fMRI evidence confirms attentional        perform certain discriminations but not others in the
modulation of invisible images in primary visual cor-         near absence of top-down attention. And they are not
tex (Bahrami et al. 2007). In conclusion, attentional         guessing. They can be quite confident of their choices
selection does not necessarily engender phenomenal            and “see,” albeit often indistinctly, what they can
sensations, although it may often do so.                      discriminate.
                                                                  The existence of such dissociations—attention
Consciousness in the Absence of Attention                     without consciousness and consciousness without
   When focusing intensely on one event, the world            attention—should not be surprising when considering
is not reduced to a tunnel, with everything outside           their different functions. Attention is a set of mecha-
the focus of attention gone: we are always aware of           nisms whereby the brain selects a subset of the incom-
some aspects of the world surrounding us, such as its         ing sensory information for higher level processing,
gist. Indeed, gist is immune from inattentional blind-        while the nonattended portions of the input are ana-
ness (Mack & Rock 1998)—when a photograph cover-              lyzed at a lower band width. For example, in primates,
ing the entire background is briefly and unexpectedly          about one million fibers leave each eye and carry on
flashed onto the screen, subjects can accurately report        the order of one megabyte per second of raw infor-
a summary of its content. In the 30 ms necessary to ap-       mation. One way to deal with this deluge of data is to
prehend the gist of a scene, top-down attention cannot        select a small fraction and process this reduced input in
play much of a role (because gist is a property asso-         real time, while the nonattended data suffer from be-
ciated with the entire image, any process that locally        nign neglect. Attention can be directed by bottom-up,
enhances features is going to be of limited use).             exogenous cues or by top-down endogenous features
   Or take the perception of a single object (say a bar) in   and can be applied to a spatially restricted part of the
an otherwise empty display, a nonecological but com-          image (focal, spotlight of attention), an attribute (e.g.,
mon arrangement in many animal and human experi-              all red objects), or to an entire object. By contrast, con-
ments. Here, what function would top-down, selective          sciousness appears to be involved in providing a kind
attention need to perform without any competing item          of “executive summary” of the current situation that
in or around fixation? Indeed, the most popular neu-           is useful for decision making, planning, and learning
ronal model of attention, biased competition (Desimone        (Baars).
& Duncan 1995), predicts that in the absence of com-
petition, no or little attentional enhancement occurs,
yet we are perfectly aware of the object and its back-        Changes in the Level of Consciousness
ground.
   In a dual-task paradigms, the subject’s attention is          In neurology, a distinction is traditionally made be-
drawn to a demanding central task, while at the same          tween the level of consciousness and the content of
time a secondary stimulus is flashed somewhere in the          consciousness. When you fall asleep, for example, the
periphery. Using the identical retinal layout, the sub-       level of consciousness decreases to the point that you
ject either performs the central task, the peripheral         become virtually unconscious—the degree to which
task, or both simultaneously (Sperling & Dosher 1986;         you are conscious (of anything) becomes progressively
Braun & Sagi 1990; Braun & Julesz 1998). With fo-             less and less. The content of consciousness, instead,
cal attention busy at the center, the subject can still       refers to the particular experience you’re having at any
distinguish a natural scene containing an animal (or          given time, for the same level of consciousness. It is use-
a vehicle) from one that does not include an animal           ful to maintain this distinction when considering the
Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness                                                          243


NCC, and begin by considering changes in the level of          An intriguing possibility is that changes in the level
consciousness.                                              of consciousness during sleep may be related to the de-
                                                            gree of bistability of thalamocortical networks (Tononi
                        Sleep                               2004b; Massimini et al. 2007). In a recent study, tran-
   Sleep offers a commonplace, daily demonstration          scranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) was used in con-
that the level of consciousness can change dramati-         junction with high-density EEG to record cortical
cally. In the laboratory, a subject is awakened during      evoked responses to direct stimulation in waking and
different stages of sleep and asked to report “anything     sleep (Massimini et al. 2005; Massimini et al. 2007).
that was going through your mind just before waking         During wakefulness, TMS induced a sustained re-
up.” What is most noteworthy for the present pur-           sponse made of rapidly changing patterns of activity
poses is that a number of awakenings from non-REM           that persisted until 300 ms and involved the sequen-
(NREM) sleep, especially early in the night when EEG        tial activation of specific brain areas, depending on
slow waves are prevalent, can yield no report what-         the precise site of stimulation. During early NREM
soever. Thus, early slow-wave sleep is the only phase       sleep, however, the brain response to TMS changed
of adult life during which healthy human subjects may       markedly. When applied to lateral cortical regions,
deny that they were experiencing anything at all. When      the activity evoked by TMS remained localized to the
present, reports from NREM sleep early in the night         site of stimulation, without activating connected brain
are often short and thought-like. However, especially       regions, and lasted for less than 150 ms (Massimini
later in the night, reports from NREM sleep can be          et al. 2005). This finding indicates that during early
longer, more hallucinatory and, generally speaking,         NREM sleep, when the level of consciousness is re-
more dream-like. On the other hand, awakenings dur-         duced, effective connectivity among cortical regions
ing REM sleep almost always yield dreams—vivid con-         breaks down, implying a corresponding breakdown of
scious experiences, sometimes organized within a com-       cortical integration. Computer simulations suggest that
plex narrative structure (Hobson et al. 2000; Hobson        this breakdown of effective connectivity may be due to
& Pace-Schott 2002).                                        the induction of a local down state (Esser & Tononi, in
   What are the processes underlying the fading of the      preparation). When applied over centromedian pari-
level of consciousness during early slow-wave sleep?        etal regions, each TMS pulse triggered a stereotypical
Though metabolic rates decrease in many cortical ar-        response implying the induction of a global down state:
eas, especially frontal and parietal areas, the thalam-     a full-fledged, high-amplitude slow wave (Massimini et
ocortical system is far from shutting down. Instead,        al. 2007) that closely resembled spontaneous ones and
triggered by a decrease in acetylcholine and other          that traveled through much of the cortex (Massimini
modulators, cortical and thalamic neurons undergo           et al. 2004). Such stereotypical responses could be in-
slow oscillations (1 Hz or less) between an up and          duced even when, for the preceding seconds, there
a down state (Steriade et al. 2001). During the up          were no slow waves in the spontaneous EEG, indicat-
state, cortical cells remain depolarized at waking levels   ing that perturbations can reveal the potential bista-
for around a second and fire at waking rates, often          bility of a system irrespective of its observed state. Al-
in the gamma range (Destexhe et al. 2007). How-             together, these TMS–EEG measurements suggest that
ever, the up state of NREM sleep is not stable as           the sleeping brain, despite being active and reactive,
in wakefulness and REM sleep, but it is inherently          becomes inherently bistable: it either breaks down in
bistable. The longer neurons remain depolarized, the        causally independent modules or bursts into a global,
more likely they become to precipitate into a hyper-        stereotypical response. By contrast, during REM sleep
polarized down state—a complete cessation of synap-         late in the night, when dreams become long and vivid
tic activity that can last for a tenth of a second or       and consciousness returns to levels close to those of
more—after which they revert to another up state.           wakefulness, the responses to TMS also recover and
The transition from up to down states appears to be         come to resemble more closely those observed dur-
due to depolarization-dependent potassium currents          ing wakefulness: evoked patterns of activity become
and to short-term synaptic depression, both of which        more complex and spatially differentiated, although
increase with the amount of prior activation (Steri-        some late components are still missing (Massimini &
ade 2003). The slow oscillation is found in virtually       Tononi, unpublished).
every cortical neuron and is synchronized across the
cortical mantle by cortico-cortical connections, which                           Anesthesia
is why the EEG records high-voltage, low-frequency             The most common among exogenous manip-
waves.                                                      ulations of the level of consciousness is general
244                                                                     Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

anesthesia. Anesthetics come in two main classes: intra-      of action of several anesthetics is the posterior cingu-
venous agents used for induction, such as propofol and        late/medial parietal cortical areas, as well as the me-
ketamine, which are generally administered together           dial basal forebrain). However, both PET and fMRI
with sedatives such as midazolam and dexmedeto-               signals mostly reflect synaptic activity rather than cel-
midine; and inhaled agents, such as isoflurane,                lular firing, and the thalamus receives a massive in-
sevoflurane, and desflurane or the gases xenon and              nervation from cortex. Moreover, the relative reduc-
nitrous oxide. The doses of inhaled anesthetics are           tion in thalamic activity occurs on a background of a
usually referred to their minimum alveolar concen-            marked decrease in global metabolism (30–60%) that
tration (MAC): a MAC value of 1 is the dose that              involves many cortical regions. Thus, thalamic activity
prevents movement in 50% of subjects in response              as recorded by neuroimaging may represent an es-
to a painful surgical stimulation. At low MAC values          pecially sensitive, localized readout of the extent of
(0.1–0.2) anesthetics produce amnesia, first explicit and      widespread cortical deactivation, rather than the final
then implicit. Frequently there are distortions of time       common pathway of unconsciousness (Ori et al. 1986).
perception, such as slowing down and fragmentation,           In fact, spontaneous thalamic firing in animal models
and a feeling of disconnection from the environment.          of anesthesia is mostly driven by corticothalamic feed-
Also, at low MAC values anesthetics produce increas-          back (Vahle-Hinz et al. 2007), and the metabolic effects
ing sleepiness and make arousal progressively more dif-       of enflurane on the thalamus can be abolished by an
ficult, suggesting that to some extent they can mimic          ipsilateral cortical ablation (Nakakimura et al. 1988),
neurophysiological events underlying sleep. At around         suggesting that the switch in thalamic unit activity is
0.3 MAC people experience a decrease in the level             driven primarily through a reduction in afferent cor-
of consciousness, also described as a “shrinking” in          ticothalamic feedback more than by a direct effect of
the field of consciousness, as if they were kept on the        anesthesia on thalamic neurons. Recently, thalamic ac-
verge of falling asleep. MAC-awake, usually around            tivity was recorded using depth electrodes in a patient
0.3–0.4 MAC, is the point at which response to ver-           undergoing anesthesia for the implant of a deep brain
bal command is lost in 50% of patients and is con-            stimulator (Velly et al. 2007). With either propofol or
sidered the point at which consciousness is lost (LOC).       sevoflurane, when the patient lost consciousness, the
The transition to unconsciousness (LOC) appears to be         cortical EEG changed dramatically. However, there
rather brusque, not unlike the collapse of muscle tone        was little change in the thalamic EEG until almost
that usually accompanies it, suggesting that neural pro-      10 min later. This result implies that the deactivation
cesses underlying consciousness change in a nonlinear         of cortex alone is sufficient for loss of consciousness,
manner. At concentrations above LOC, movements                and conversely that thalamic activity alone is insuffi-
are still possible, especially partially coordinated re-      cient to maintain it.
sponses to painful stimuli, suggesting that some degree           These findings do not imply that the thalamus is
of “unconscious” processing is still possible. Complete       irrelevant, but rather suggest that its effects on con-
unresponsiveness is usually obtained just above MAC           sciousness are largely accounted for by its effects on
of 1.0.                                                       cortical circuits, most notably by providing a tonic fa-
   At the cellular level, many anesthetics have mixed ef-     cilitatory action that can help to restore consciousness,
fects, but the overall result is a decrease in neuronal ex-   or cause its collapse when it fails. A dramatic demon-
citability by either increasing inhibition or decreasing      stration is provided by a recent study, where rats kept
excitation. Most anesthetics act by enhancing GABA            under anesthetic concentration of sevoflurane could be
inhibition or by hyperpolarizing cells through an in-         awakened by a minute injection of nicotinic agents in
crease of potassium-leak currents. They can also inter-       an intralaminar thalamic nucleus (Alkire et al. 2007).
fere with glutamatergic transmission and antagonize           Conversely, GABA agonists infused into the same side
acetylcholine at nicotinic receptors (Campagna et al.         caused an immediate loss of consciousness (Miller et al.
2003; Franks 2006). But what are critical circuits me-        1989; Miller & Ferrendelli 1990) (though nicotinic an-
diating the LOC induced by anesthetics?                       tagonists did not).
   A considerable number of neuroimaging studies in
humans have recently shed some light on this issue                      Coma and Vegetative States
(Alkire & Miller 2005). The most consistent effects              While consciousness may nearly fade during cer-
produced by most anesthetics at LOC is a reduction            tain phases of sleep and be kept at very low lev-
of thalamic metabolism and blood flow, suggesting the          els for a prescribed period during general anesthe-
possibility that the thalamus may serve as a conscious-       sia, coma and vegetative states are characterized by
ness switch (Alkire et al. 2000). (Another common site        a loss of consciousness that is hard or impossible to
Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness                                                            245


reverse. Coma—an enduring sleep-like state of immo-           cortices (Laureys et al. 2000a). A recent study by Niko
bility with eyes closed from which the patient cannot be      Schiff and colleagues shows the role of the thalamus
aroused—represents the paradigmatic form of patho-            even more dramatically: bilateral deep brain electri-
logical loss of consciousness. Typically, coma is caused      cal stimulation of the central thalamus restored a de-
by a suppression of thalamocortical function by drugs,        gree of behavioral responsiveness in a patient who had
toxins, or internal metabolic derangements. Other             remained in a minimally conscious state for 6 years
causes of coma are head trauma, strokes, or hypoxia           following brain trauma (Schiff et al. 2007).
due to heart failure, which again cause widespread de-           In vegetative states, brain metabolism is globally re-
struction of thalamocortical circuits. Smaller lesions of     duced by 50 to 60%, most notably in regions such as the
the reticular activating system can also cause uncon-         posterior cingulate cortex and the precuneus (Laureys
sciousness, presumably by deactivating the thalamo-           et al. 2004; Schiff 2006a). These are also the areas that
cortical system indirectly.                                   reactivate most reliably if a patient regains conscious-
   Patients who survive a coma may recover, while             ness. A recent case study reported an extraordinary re-
others enter the so-called vegetative state, in which         covery of verbal communication and motor function in
eyes reopen, giving the appearance of wakefulness, but        a patient who had remained in a minimally conscious
unresponsiveness persists. Soon, regular sleep/waking         state for 19 years (Voss et al. 2006). Diffusion tensor
cycles follow. Respiration, other autonomic functions         MRI showed increased fractional anisotropy (assumed
and brainstem functions are relatively preserved, and         to reflect myelinated fiber density) in posteromedial
stereotypic, reflex-like responses can occur, including        cortices, encompassing cuneus and precuneus. These
yawning and grunting, but no purposeful behavior. Pa-         same areas showed increased glucose metabolism as
tients may remain vegetative for a long time or may           studied by PET scanning, likely reflecting the neu-
emerge to a “minimally conscious state.” This is dis-         ronal regrowth paralleling the patient’s clinical recov-
tinguished from the vegetative state by the occasional        ery. This and other neuroimaging studies of vegetative
occurrence of some behaviors that do not appear to be         or minimally conscious patients are demonstrating ever
purely reflexive, suggesting that some degree of con-          more clearly that a purely clinical diagnosis of persis-
sciousness may be present.                                    tent loss of consciousness may at times be dramatically
   Post-mortem analysis in vegetative patients reveals        inaccurate. It was already known that patients with
that the brainstem and hypothalamus, and specifi-              locked-in syndromes due to pontine lesions that left
cally the reticular activating system, are largely spared,    them almost completely paralyzed may seem unre-
which explains why patients look awake. Usually the           sponsive, but if they preserve even a minimal ability
vegetative state is due to widespread lesions of gray         to signal (typically by moving an eye or eyelid up or
matter in neocortex and thalamus, to widespread               down) they can communicate a rich subjective expe-
white-matter damage and diffuse axonal injury, or to          rience. What about patients who show no voluntary
bilateral thalamic lesions, especially of the paramedian      movement at all? Several imaging studies have now
thalamic nuclei. It is not clear whether thalamic dam-        shown that, even in completely unresponsive patients,
age is largely a reflection of diffuse cortical damage         as long as significant portions of the thalamocortical
(as in metabolic studies of anesthesia, changes in the        system are preserved, cognitive stimuli can induce pat-
thalamus are much more concentrated and therefore             terns of activation similar to those seen in healthy sub-
easier to document than changes in cortex) or whether         jects (Laureys et al. 2004; Schiff 2006b). As we have
even isolated thalamic damage can cause persistent            seen in a previous section, stimuli that are not per-
unconsciousness. Matrix, calbindin-positive thalamic          ceived consciously can still activate appropriate brain
cells, which are most numerous within intralaminar            areas. Thus, inferring the presence of consciousness
nuclei, project diffusely to supragranular layers of cor-     may be unwarranted. However, in a recent, thought-
tex (Jones 1998) where they facilitate coherent high-         provoking study, a clinically vegetative, seemingly un-
frequency oscillations (Joliot et al. 1994). Such cells may   responsive patient was put in the scanner and asked
be especially important in enabling effective interac-        to imagine playing tennis or navigating through her
tions among many cortical regions: if their activating        room. Remarkably, the patient showed fMRI activa-
function is lost, patients may remain vegetative even         tion patterns of the appropriate cortical regions, exactly
though cortical tissue may be relatively intact. Indeed,      like healthy subjects. Obviously, these activations could
Steven Laureys and colleagues showed that recovery            not be due to unconscious processing of stimuli (Owen
from a vegetative state was associated with the restora-      et al. 2006). Of note, this patient had widespread
tion of functional connectivity between intralaminar          frontal lesions, while posterior cortex was largely
thalamic nuclei and prefrontal and anterior cingulate         preserved.
246                                                                    Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences


                       Seizures                             tivity less focally than initially thought (Blumenfeld &
   The abnormal, hypersynchronous discharge of neu-         Taylor 2003; Blumenfeld et al. 2003; Blumenfeld et al.
rons is a frequent cause of short-lasting impairments of    2004; Blumenfeld 2005). In fact, it now appears that
consciousness. Consciousness is lost or severely affected   all seizures causing an impairment of consciousness
in so-called generalized seizures, such as absence and      are associated with changes in activity in three sets of
tonic-clonic seizures, and to a lesser extent in complex    brain areas, namely: i) increased activity in the upper
partial seizures. Absence seizures, which are more fre-     brainstem and medial thalamus; ii) decreased activity
quent in children, are momentary lapses of conscious-       in the anterior and posterior cingulate, medial frontal
ness during which a child stops what she was doing          cortex, and precuneus; iii) altered activity in the lateral
and stares straight ahead blankly. Absence seizures are     and orbital frontal cortex and in the lateral parietal
accompanied by spike-and-wave complexes at around           cortex. In tonic-clonic seizures, fronto-parietal associ-
3 Hz in the EEG, reflecting cycles of synchronous fir-        ation areas show increased activity, while the pattern is
ing and silence of large numbers of neurons. There          more complex and variable in absence seizures, though
is great variability in the degree of unresponsiveness      parietal areas are usually deactivated. Complex partial
both across subjects and, within the same subject, be-      seizures show decreased activity in frontal and parietal
tween seizures. Sometimes, simple behaviors such as         association cortex, which is associated with the onset
repetitive tapping or counting can proceed unimpaired       of slow waves similar to those of sleep or anesthesia
during the seizures, but more complex tasks come to a       (rather than to epileptiform discharges).
halt.                                                          At this stage, it is not clear which of these three sets
   Generalized convulsive seizures usually comprise a       of areas, alone or in combination, are crucial for the
tonic phase of muscle stiffening, followed by a clonic      loss of consciousness. However, two things are clear:
phase with jerking of the arms and legs. After the con-     first, the areas involved in the loss of consciousness
vulsion the person may be lethargic or in a state of        associated with seizures correspond to those affected
confusion for minutes up to hours. During the tonic         in sleep, anesthesia, and the vegetative state, pointing
phase of a convulsive seizure neural activity is greatly    to a common substrate for the most common forms of
increased, as indicated by high frequency activity in       loss of consciousness; and second, especially during the
the EEG. The clonic phase is accompanied by syn-            tonic phase of convulsive seizures, it would seem that
chronous spikes and waves in the EEG, correspond-           consciousness is lost when neurons are excessively and
ing to millions of neurons alternately firing in strong      synchronously active, rather than inactive.
bursts and turning silent. Loss of consciousness during
the tonic phase of generalized seizures is noteworthy
because it occurs at times when neuronal activity is               Changes in the Content of
extremely high and synchronous.                                Consciousness—-Localizing the NCC
   Partial complex seizures often begin with strange
abdominal sensations, fears, premonitions, or auto-             As we have seen, much can be learned by studying
matic gestures. The person progressively loses contact      how brain activity changes with changes in the overall
with the environment, exhibits a fixed stare, and is         level of consciousness. A complementary approach is
unable to respond adequately to questions or com-           to examine how brain activity changes when a specific
mands. Stereotyped, automatic movements are com-            content of consciousness changes—for example, a vi-
mon. Complex partial seizures usually last from 15 sec      sual stimulus becomes visible or invisible—while every-
to 3 min. Seizure activity is usually localized to the      thing else, including the overall level of consciousness
medial temporal lobe.                                       as well as the sensory input, remains as constant as pos-
   The diagnosis of seizures is made through clini-         sible. Recording spike trains from individual neurons
cal observation and EEG recordings. In absence and          or measuring hemodynamic signals while the subject
tonic-clonic seizures the scalp EEG shows diffuse ab-       is looking at a stimulus in an MR scanner allows re-
normalities, suggesting a generalized involvement of        searchers to investigate what kind of neuronal activity
brain networks, whereas in partial complex seizures         is correlated with the conscious perception of the stim-
the abnormalities are confined to a medial temporal fo-      ulus rather than with the mere presentation of the
cus on one side. However, neuroimaging studies using        stimulus. The goal is to follow the footprints of con-
SPECT, PET, and fMRI, and depth EEG recordings              sciousness in the brain by ultimately identifying the
in humans and animals have revealed that general-           neural correlates of consciousness (NCC)—the mini-
ized seizures do not affect all brain areas indiscrimi-     mal neuronal mechanisms that are jointly sufficient for
nately, whereas complex partial seizures alter brain ac-    any one specific conscious percept (Crick & Koch 1995,
Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness                                                            247


1998, 2003). Thus, every phenomenal, subjective state           A Test Case: The NCC in Visual Cortex
will have associated NCC: one for seeing a red patch,           Many experiments exploit perceptual illusions in
another one for seeing grandmother, yet a third one          which the physical stimulus remains fixed while the per-
for hearing a siren, another one for feeling free to act     cept fluctuates. The best known example is the Necker
one way or another and so on. Perturbing or inactivat-       cube, whose 12 lines can be perceived in one of two
ing the NCC for any one specific conscious experience         different ways in depth. Another perceptual illusion
will affect the percept or cause it to disappear. If the     that is easy to vary parametrically is binocular rivalry
NCC could be induced artificially, for instance by cor-       (Blake & Logothetis 2002): a small image, for example
tical microstimulation in a prosthetic device or during      a horizontal grating, is presented to the left eye and an-
neurosurgery, the subject will experience the associated     other image, for example a vertical grating, is shown
percept. This definition of the NCC stresses the word         to the corresponding location in the right eye. In spite
“minimal,” because the question of interest is which         of the constant visual stimulus, observers consciously
subcomponents of the brain are actually needed. For          see the horizontal grating alternate every few seconds
instance, while neural activity in the cerebellum may        with the vertical one. The brain does not allow for the
ultimately affect some behaviors elicited by the presen-     simultaneous perception of both images.
tation of a stimulus (such as eye movements), it is likely      Macaque monkeys can be trained to report whether
that such activity has little to do with the generation of   they see the left or the right image. The distribution of
the conscious percept of that stimulus, and thus is not      the switching times and the way in which changing the
part of the NCC.                                             contrast in one eye affects the reports leaves little doubt
   Many questions can be asked: What characterizes           that monkeys and humans experience the same basic
the NCC for a specific experience? What do the NCC            phenomenon. In a series of elegant experiments, Lo-
for different experiences have in common? Do the             gothetis and colleagues (Leopold & Logothetis 1996;
NCC involve just the thalamocortical system, or do           Logothetis 1998) recorded from a variety of visual cor-
they extend to structures such as the hippocampus,           tical areas in the awake macaque monkey while the
the claustrum, or the basal ganglia? Do they involve all     animal performed a binocular rivalry task. In primary
pyramidal neurons in cortex at any given point in time?      visual cortex (V1), only a small fraction of cells weakly
Or only a subset of cells in frontal lobes that project to   modulated their response as a function of the percept of
the sensory cortices in the back? Only layer 5 cortical      the monkey. The majority of cells responded to one or
cells? Neurons that fire in a phasic, synchronous, or         the other retinal stimulus with little regard to what the
oscillatory manner? Or neurons that are included in          animal perceived at the time. In contrast, in a high-
reentrant loops? These are some of the proposals that        level cortical area such as the inferior temporal (IT)
have been advanced over the past years (Chalmers             cortex along the ventral pathway, almost all neurons
2000).                                                       responded only to the perceptual dominant stimulus,
   Much of the contemporary work aimed at char-              that is, to the stimulus that was being reported. For
acterizing the NCC has concentrated on changes in            example, when a face and a more abstract design were
specific visual contents of consciousness (or awareness,      presented, one of these to each eye, a “face” cell fired
which is here used interchangeably), in part because         only when the animal indicated by its performance
visual experience is easy to manipulate experimentally,      that it saw the face and not the design presented to
and in part because more is known about the anatomy          the other eye. This result implies that the NCC involve
and function of visual areas in primates than about          activity in neurons in inferior temporal cortex (but not,
any other brain regions. Visual psychologists have per-      of course, that the NCC are local to IT).
fected a number of techniques—masking, binocular                In a related perceptual phenomenon, flash suppres-
rivalry, continuous flash suppression, motion-induced         sion (Wolfe 1984), the percept associated with an image
blindness, change blindness, inattentional blindness—        projected into one eye is suppressed by flashing another
in which the seemingly simple and unambiguous rela-          image into the other eye (while the original image re-
tionship between a physical stimulus in the world, the       mains). A methodological advantage over binocular
resulting neural activity, and its associated percept is     rivalry is that the timing of the perceptual transition
disrupted (Kim & Blake 2005). We first consider what          is determined by an external trigger rather than by
such approaches have revealed about the brain areas          an internal event. The majority of responsive cells in
that underlie the NCC, focusing specifically on the vi-       inferior temporal cortex and in the superior temporal
sual system. In the following sections we ask whether        sulcus follow the monkey’s behavior—and therefore its
the NCC for visual percepts corresponds to some spe-         percept. That is, when the animal perceives a cell’s
cial kind of neural activity.                                preferred stimulus, the neuron fires; when the stimulus
248                                                                       Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

is present on the retina but is perceptually suppressed,       tually invisible line drawings can still be modulated
the cell falls silent, even though legions of V1 neu-          by selective visual attention. Also, Haynes and Rees
rons fire vigorously to the same stimulus (Sheinberg            (2005) exploited multivariate decoding techniques to
& Logothetis 1997). Single neuron recordings in the            read out perceptually suppressed information (the ori-
medial temporal lobe of epileptic patients during flash         entation of a masked stimulus) from V1 BOLD ac-
suppression likewise demonstrate abolition of their re-        tivity, even though the stimulus orientation was so effi-
sponses when their preferred stimulus is present on the        ciently masked that subjects performed at chance levels
retina but not seen (Kreiman et al. 2002).                     when trying to guess the orientation. That is, although
   In a powerful combination of binocular rivalry and          subjects did not give any behavioral indication that
flash suppression, a stationary image in one eye can be         they saw the orientation of the stimulus, its slant could
suppressed for minutes on end by continuously flash-            be predicted on a single-trial basis with better-than-
ing different images into the other eye (continuous flash       chance odds from the V1 (but not from V2 or V3)
suppression; Tsuchiya & Koch 2005). This paradigm              BOLD signal.
lends itself naturally to further investigation of the rela-      In conclusion, information pertaining to visual stim-
tionship between neural activity—whether assayed at            ulus can be registered in primary visual cortex that may
the single neuron or at the brain voxel level—and con-         or may not be accessible to the subject. It may be mod-
scious perception. Imaging experiments with such per-          ulated by attention, but it does not appear to correlate
ceptual illusions demonstrate quite conclusively that          directly with the subject’s percept. In that sense much
BOLD activity in the upper stages of the ventral path-         of the neural activity in V1 probably does not belong
way (e.g., the fusiform face area and the parahippocam-        to the NCC. Moreover, as suggested by PET exper-
pal place area) follow the percept and not simply the          iments in patients in a persistent vegetative state, in
retinal stimulus (Tong et al. 1998; Rees & Frith 2007).        whom stimuli evoked strong but localized activity in
   There is a lively debate about the extent to which          primary auditory and primary somatosensory cortices
neurons in primary visual cortex simply encode the             (Laureys et al. 2000b; Laureys et al. 2002), it may well
visual stimulus or are directly contributing to the sub-       be that none of the primary sensory cortices contributes
ject’s conscious percept (Tong 2003). That is, is V1           directly to sensory consciousness.
part of the NCC (Crick & Koch 1995)? It is clear that
retinal neurons are not part of the NCC for visual ex-
periences. While retinal neurons often correlate with           Consciousness and Neural Dynamics
visual experience, the spiking activity of retinal gan-
glion cells does not accord with visual experience (e.g.,          The studies discussed above indicate that, even
there are no photoreceptors at the blind spot; yet no          within the cerebral cortex, changes in neural activity do
hole in the field of view is apparent, in dreams vivid im-      not necessarily correlate with changes in conscious ex-
agery occurs despite closed eyes, and so on). A number         perience. Also, we saw earlier that most of the cortex is
of compelling observations link perception with fMRI           active during early NREM sleep and anesthesia, not to
BOLD activity in human V1 and even in the lateral              mention during generalized seizures, but subjects have
geniculate nucleus (LGN) (Tong et al. 1998; Lee et             little conscious content to report. Thus, it is natural to
al. 2005). These data are at odds with single-neuron           suggest that some additional dynamic feature of neural
recordings from the monkey. This discrepancy is prob-          activity must be present to generate conscious content.
ably explained by the often tight relationship between         Here we consider the roles of i) sustained versus phasic
consciousness and attention that was mentioned above           activity, ii) reentrant versus feedforward activity, and
(see section “Consciousness and Attention”). Unless at-        iii) synchronous or oscillatory activity.
tentional effects are carefully controlled for, their neu-
ral correlates cannot be untangled from those of con-                  Sustained versus Phasic Activity
sciousness (Huk et al. 2001; Tse et al. 2005). This has           A plausible idea is that neural activity may con-
now been achieved in an elegant study of Lee, Blake,           tribute to consciousness only if it is sustained for a
and Heeger (2007). Using a dual-task paradigm they             minimum period of time, perhaps around a few hun-
found that hemodynamic BOLD activity in human V1               dred ms. At the phenomenological level, there is no
reflects attentional processes but does not directly cor-       doubt that the “now” of experience unfolds at a time
relate with the conscious percept of the subject. The          scale comprised between tens and several hundred ms
experiment by Bahrami and colleagues (Bahrami et               (Bachmann 2000) and in some aspects may even stretch
al. 2007) comes to a similar conclusion—they show              to one or two seconds (Poppel & Artin 1988). Other
that the fMRI signal in V1 associated with percep-             experiments have made use of the attentional blink
Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness                                                             249


phenomenon: when an observer detects a target in a           the target, though they may deny having seen it con-
rapid stream of visual stimuli, there is a brief period of   sciously. Thus, consciousness would seem to require
time during which the detection of subsequent targets        that neural activity in appropriate brain structures lasts
is impaired. Remarkably, targets that directly follow the    for a minimum amount of time, perhaps as much as
first target are less impaired than those that follow after   is needed to guarantee interactions among multiple
200 to 400 ms (Raymond et al. 1992). By manipulat-           areas.
ing attention, identical visual stimuli can be made con-        On the other hand, other data would seem to sug-
scious or unconscious. In such studies, event-related        gest that it may actually be the phasic, onset, or off-
potentials reflecting early sensory processing (the P1        set discharge of neurons that correlates with experi-
and N1 components) were identical for seen and un-           ence. The most stringent data come again from studies
seen stimuli but quickly diverged around 270 ms, sug-        of visual masking (for a review see Macknik 2006).
gesting that stimuli only become visible when a sus-         To be effective, masking stimuli must either precede
tained wave of activation spreads through a distributed      (forward masking) or follow (backward masking) tar-
network of cortical association areas (Vogel et al. 1998;    get stimuli at appropriate time intervals and usually
Sergent et al. 2005).                                        need to be spatially contiguous. Macknik, Martinez-
    More generally, the requirement for sustained dis-       Conde, and collaborators showed, using a combina-
charge might account for why fast, reflex responses           tion of psychophysics, unit recordings in animals, and
of the kind mediated by, say, the spinal cord, do not        neuroimaging in humans, that for simple, unattended
seem to contribute to consciousness. Fast, reflex-like        target stimuli, masking stimuli suppress visibility if their
responses also take place in the cerebral cortex. For ex-    “spatiotemporal edges” overlap with the spatiotempo-
ample, the action-oriented dorsal visual stream rapidly      ral edges of the targets, that is, if they begin or end
adjusts movements that remain outside of conscious-          when target stimuli begin or end, in space and time.
ness (Goodale & Milner 2005). Perhaps these reflex-           They confirmed that such spatiotemporal edges cor-
like adjustments to fast-changing aspects of the envi-       respond to transient bursts of spikes in primary visual
ronment that must be tracked online are incompatible         cortex. If these bursts are inhibited, for example if the
with the development of sustained discharge patterns.        offset discharge elicited by the target stimulus is oblit-
By contrast, such sustained patterns may be necessary        erated by the onset of the mask, the target becomes
for the ventral stream to build a stable representation      invisible. Most likely, these spatiotemporal edges of in-
of a visual scene. By the same token, if the ventral         creased firing are both generated (target stimuli) and
stream could be forced to behave in a reflex-like man-        suppressed (masking stimuli) by mechanisms of lateral
ner, it should cease to be part of the NCC. Indeed,          inhibition, which are ubiquitous in sensory systems
this can be achieved by pushing the ventral system to        (Macknik 2006).
perform ultra-rapid categorizations such as deciding            Additional evidence for the importance of phasic,
whether a natural image contains an animal or not            transient activation of neurons in determining the visi-
(Thorpe et al. 1996; Bacon-Mace et al. 2005; Kirch-          bility of stimuli comes from studies of microsaccades—
ner & Thorpe 2006). In such cases, a sweep of activity       the small, involuntary movements that our eyes make
travels from the retina through several stages of feedfor-   continually (Martinez-Conde et al. 2004). If microsac-
ward connections along the hierarchy of ventral visual       cades are counteracted by image stabilization on the
areas, until it elicits an appropriate categorization re-    retina, stationary objects fade and become completely
sponse. This process takes as little as 150 ms, which        invisible. In a recent study (Martinez-Conde et al.
leaves only about 10 ms of processing per stage. Thus,       2006), subjects were asked to fixate a central dot (which
only a few spikes can be fired before the next stage          tends to reduce microsaccades) while attending to a
produces its output, yet they are sufficient to spec-         surrounding circle. Soon, the circle fades and merges
ify selective responses for orientation, motion, depth,      into the background (the Troxler illusion). It was found
color, shape, and even animals, faces, or places con-        that before a fading period, the probability, rate, and
veying most of the relevant information about the            magnitude of microsaccades decreased. Before transi-
stimulus (Hung et al. 2005). While this fast feedfor-        tions toward visibility, the probability, rate, and mag-
ward sweep within the ventral system is sufficient for        nitude of microsaccades increased, compatible with
the near-automatic categorization of stimuli and a be-       the hypothesis that microsaccades are indeed neces-
havioral response, it seems insufficient to generate a        sary for visibility. Importantly, in macaque monkeys,
conscious percept (VanRullen & Koch 2003). For ex-           when an optimally oriented line was centered over
ample, if another image (the mask) is flashed soon after      the receptive field of cells in V1, the cells’ activity in-
the target image, subjects are still able to categorize      creased after microsaccades and tended to emit bursts
250                                                                      Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

(Martinez-Conde et al. 2002), suggesting again that           (Hebb 1949), implementing hypothesis testing through
phasic activity may be crucial for visibility.                resonances (Grossberg 1999), linking present with past
   One should remember, however, that the impor-              (Edelman & Mountcastle 1978; Edelman 1989), and
tance of phasic discharges for stimulus awareness has         subject with object (Damasio 1999).
only been demonstrated for early visual cortex; but,              A more concrete reason why reentrant activity is
as we saw above, the NCC are more likely to lie               an attractive candidate for the NCC is that it travels
elsewhere. Psychophysically, masking is similarly effec-      through back connections, of which the cerebral cortex
tive when masking stimuli are presented monoptically          is extraordinarily rich (Felleman & Van Essen 1991).
(through the same eye as the target) and dichoptically        In primates, feedforward connections originate mainly
(through the other eye). The analysis of fMRI data            in supragranular layers and terminate in layer 4. Feed-
in humans shows that a correlate of monoptic visual           back connections instead originate in both superficial
masking can be found in all retinotopic visual areas,         and deep layers and usually terminate outside of layer
whereas dichoptic masking is only seen in retinotopic         4. The sheer abundance of back connections in sensory
areas downstream of V2 within the occipital lobe (Tse         regions suggests that they ought to serve some impor-
et al. 2005), suggesting an anatomical lower bound for        tant purpose, and giving rise to a conscious percept
the NCC. Thus, it could be that phasic onset and off-         might just fit the bill. However, back connections and
set discharges are important not in and of themselves,        associated reentrant volleys are just as numerous be-
but because they are particularly effective in activating     tween V1 and visual thalamus, which is usually denied
downstream areas that directly support the NCC. In            any direct contribution to awareness. Also, there does
these downstream areas, perhaps, the NCC may ac-              not seem to be any lack of back connections within
tually require sustained firing. Indeed, the duration of       the dorsal stream. It should be emphasized that the
the activation of face-selective neurons in IT is strongly    strength and termination pattern of back connections
correlated with the visibility of masked faces (Rolls et      seem more suited to a modulatory/synchronizing role
al. 1999).                                                    than to driving their target neurons. For example, the
                                                              focal inactivation of area 18 can slightly increase or
    Reentrant versus Feedforward Activity                     decrease discharge rates of units in area 17, but it
    Another possibility is that it is not so much sustained   does not change their feature selectivity for location
firing that triggers the awareness of a stimulus, but          and orientation (Martinez-Conde et al. 1999). Also,
rather the occurrence of a “reentrant” wave of activity       the numerosity of backward connections is a natural
(also described as recurrent, recursive, or reverberant)      consequence of the hierarchical organization of feed-
from higher to lower cortical areas. In this view, when a     forward ones. For instance, cells in the LGN are not
stimulus evokes a feedforward sweep of activity, it is not    oriented, while cells in area 17 are. To be unbiased,
seen consciously, but it becomes so when the feedfor-         feedback to any one LGN cell should come from area
ward sweep is joined by a reentrant sweep (Lamme &            17 cells of all orientations, which requires many con-
Roelfsema 2000). This logic could apply both to early         nections; on the other hand, since at any given time
sensory areas such as V1 and to higher areas such as IT.      only area 17 cells corresponding to a given orientation
For example, when face neurons in the fusiform face           would be active, feedback effects would not be strong.
area are first activated, we would not see a face con-         If they were, properties of area 17 cells, such as orienta-
sciously, although we could turn our eyes toward it or        tion selectivity, would be transferred upon LGN cells,
press a button to indicate our unconscious categoriza-        which they are not (to a first approximation). Back-
tion as a face. However, when face-selective neurons          ward signals certainly play a role in sensory function:
receive a backward volley from some higher area, for          for instance, they can mediate some extraclassical re-
example frontal cortex, the face would become visible.        ceptive field effects, provide a natural substrate for both
    This view is based on several considerations. An im-      attentional modulation and imagery, and can perhaps
portant one, though rarely confessed, is that a mere          dynamically route feedforward processing according
sequence of feedforward processing steps seems far            to prior expectations. But are backward signals really
too “straightforward” and mechanical to offer a sub-          critical for consciousness?
strate for subjective experience. Reentrant processes,            The most intriguing data in support of a role for
by “closing the loop” between past and present activ-         reentrant activity in conscious perception have come
ity, or between predicted and actual versions of the          from neurophysiological experiments. In awake mon-
input, would seem to provide a more fertile substrate         keys trained to signal whether or not they see a salient
for giving rise to reverberations (Lorente de N´ 1938),
                                                   o          figure on a background, the early, feedforward response
generating emergent properties through cell assemblies        of V1 neurons was the same, no matter whether or not
Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness                                                         251


the monkey saw the figure (Super et al. 2001). How-          stimuli that are processed in visual cortex. If, around
ever, a later response component was suppressed when        100 ms later, a TMS pulse was applied to V1, the stim-
the monkey did not see the figure. Light anesthesia also     ulus became perceptually invisible, although on forced
eliminated this later component without affecting the       choice subjects could still discriminate orientation or
initial response. Late components are thought to reflect     color. This result indicates that, without any overt par-
reentrant volleys from higher areas, although other         ticipation of V1, stimuli can reach extrastriate areas
studies have disputed this claim (Rossi et al. 2001).       without eliciting a conscious percept, just as in blind-
The late response component crucial for the visibil-        sight patients. It also suggests that, since the forward
ity of stimuli under backward masking might also be         sweep reaches V1 after just 30 or 40 ms, the TMS pulse
due to a reentrant volley (Lamme & Roelfsema 2000).         may abolish the awareness of the stimulus not so much
In this case the timing of maximal backward mask-           by blocking feedforward transmission as by interfer-
ing should be independent of target duration, since it      ing with the backward volley (see also Ro et al. 2003).
would be determined exclusively by the time needed          On the other hand, it cannot be ruled out that the
for the early component to travel to higher areas and       TMS pulse may act instead by triggering a cortical–
return to primary visual cortex. Instead, the timing of     thalamo–cortical volley that interferes with the offset
maximal masking depends on the timing of target off-        discharge triggered by the stimulus, as may indeed be
set, suggesting that the component that is obliterated      the case in backward masking.
is a feedforward offset discharge, not a reentrant one         Yet another study, this time using fMRI, examined
(Macknik 2006). Moreover, the late component can be         the neural correlates of brightness (perceptual light-
dissociated from a behavioral response simply by rais-      ness) using backward masking. The psychometric vis-
ing the decision criterion (Super et al. 2001), and it      ibility function was not correlated with the stimulated
can occur in the absence of report during change and        portion of V1, but with downstream visual regions, in-
inattentional blindness (Scholte et al. 2006). Perhaps in   cluding fusiform cortex, parietal–functional areas, and
such cases subjective experience is present but, due to     with the sectors of V1 responding to the unstimulated
an insufficient involvement of frontal areas, it cannot be   surround (Haynes et al. 2005). Remarkably, visibility
reported (Block 2005; Tsuchiya & Koch 2005; Lamme           was also correlated with the amount of coupling (ef-
2006). But then, by the same token, why should we           fective connectivity) between fusiform cortex and the
rule out subjective experience during the feedforward       portion of V1 that responded to the surround. Once
sweep?                                                      again, this result could be explained by the activation
    Another main source of evidence for a role of reen-     of reentrant connections, though fMRI cannot distin-
trant volleys in consciousness comes from experiments       guish between forward and backward influences.
using TMS. In an early experiment, Pascual-Leone
and Walsh applied TMS to V5 to elicit large, mov-                  Synchronization and Oscillations
ing phosphenes (Pascual-Leone & Walsh 2001). They              Another influential idea is that consciousness may
then applied another, subthreshold TMS pulse to a           require the synchronization, at a fine temporal scale,
corresponding location in V1. When TMS to V1 was            of large populations of neurons distributed over many
delivered after TMS to V5 (+5 to +45 ms), subjects          cortical areas, in particular via rhythmic discharges
often did not see the V5 phosphene, and when they           in the gamma range (30–70 Hz and beyond) (Crick
saw one, it was not moving. Their interpretation was        & Koch 1990). The emphasis on synchrony ties in
that disruption of activity in V1 at the time of arrival    well with the common assumption that consciousness
of a reentrant volley from V5 interferes with the ex-       requires the “binding” together of a multitude of at-
perience of attributes encoded by V5. In a subsequent       tributes within a single experience, as when we see
study (Silvanto et al. 2005), it was shown that, when a     a rich visual scene containing multiple objects and
subthreshold pulse was applied over V5, followed 10         attributes that is nevertheless perceived as a unified
− 40 ms later by a suprathreshold pulse over V1, sub-       whole (Singer 1999). According to this view, the NCC
jects reported a V5-like phosphene (large and moving),      of such an experience would include two aspects: first,
rather than a V1 phosphene (small and stationary).          the underlying activation pattern (groups of neurons
Their interpretation was that activity in V5 that, on       that have increased their firing rates) would be widely
its own, is insufficient to induce a moving percept can      distributed across different areas of the cerebral cor-
produce such a percept if the level of induced activity     tex, each specialized in signaling a different object
in V1 is high enough.                                       or attribute within the scene; and second, the firing
    In another study (Boyer et al. 2005), subjects where    of these activated neurons would be synchronized on
shown either an oriented bar or a colored patch—            a fast time scale to signal their binding into a single
252                                                                     Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

percept. In this respect, synchrony seems ideally suited     consciously perceived words induced theta oscillations
to signal relatedness: for example, in the presence of a     in multiple cortical regions until the test stimulus was
red square, some neurons would respond to the pres-          presented and a decision reached, while a burst of
ence of a square, while others would respond to the          gamma activity occurred over central and frontal leads
presence of the color red. If they synchronize at a fast     just prior to and during the presentation of the test
time scale, they would indicate to other groups of neu-      stimulus. Importantly, the earliest event distinguishing
rons that there is a red square, “binding” the two fea-      conscious and unconscious processing was not visi-
tures together (Tononi et al. 1992). By contrast, signal-    ble in the power changes of oscillations but in their
ing relatedness by increased firing rates alone would be      phase locking. About 180 ms after presentation of stim-
more cumbersome and probably slower (Singer 1999).           uli that were consciously perceived, induced gamma
Also, fine-temporal-scale synchrony has the welcome           oscillations recorded from a large number of regions
property of disambiguating among multiple objects—           exhibited precise phase locking both within and across
if a green cross were present simultaneously with the        hemispheres for around 100 ms. These results have
red square, cross and green neurons would also be ac-        been interpreted to indicate that a transient event of
tive, but false conjunctions would be avoided by precise     gamma synchrony resets multiple parallel processes to
phase locking (Tononi et al. 1992). Moreover, compu-         a common time frame. The global theta rhythm that
tational models predict that, for the same level of firing,   follows after this trigger event could provide the time
synchronous input is more effective on target neurons        frame for allowing a global integration of information
than asynchronous input (Abeles 1991; Tononi et al.          provided by sensory inputs and internal sources. Or
1992), and indeed synchrony makes a difference to the        perhaps beta–gamma synchrony could enable the in-
outputs to the rest of the brain (Brecht et al. 1999;        tegration of activity patterns within local cortical areas,
Schoffelen et al. 2005). Finally, large-scale models pre-    while theta synchrony would permit the integration of
dict that synchrony in the gamma range occurs due to         more globally distributed patterns: the more global the
the reciprocal connectivity and loops within the thala-      representation, the longer the time scale for the inte-
mocortical system (Lumer et al. 1997a, b), and indeed        gration of distributed information.
phase alignment between distant groups of neurons in            It would be premature to conclude, however, that
the gamma range anticipates by a few ms an increase          synchrony in one or another frequency band is neces-
in gamma-band power (Womelsdorf et al. 2007). In             sarily a marker of NCC. As revealed by an increasing
this respect, oscillatory activity, even when subthresh-     number of EEG, MEG, electrocorticography, and mul-
old, could further facilitate synchronous interactions       tiunit recordings, cognitive tasks are associated with
by biasing neurons to discharge within the same time         complex modes of synchronous coupling among pop-
frame (Engel et al. 2001).                                   ulations of neurons that shift rapidly both within and
   Experimental evidence concerning the role of syn-         across different frequency bands, within and between
chrony/synchronous oscillations in perceptual oper-          areas, and in relation to the timing of the task (Wom-
ations was initially obtained in primary visual areas        elsdorf et al. 2007). It would rather seem that, given
of anesthetized animals (for a review see Singer &           the brain’s remarkable connectivity, synchrony is an in-
Gray 1995). For example, in primary visual cortex,           evitable accompaniment of neural activity, and that it
neurons have been found that respond to a coher-             is bound to change just as activity patterns change,
ent object by synchronizing their firing in the gamma         depending on the precise experimental conditions.
range. Stimulus-specific, gamma-range synchroniza-            Whether a particular kind of synchrony, for example
tion is greatly facilitated when the EEG is activated        in the gamma range, is uniquely associated with con-
by stimulating the mesencephalic reticular formation         sciousness is still unclear. For example, high beta and
(Munk et al. 1996; Herculano-Houzel et al. 1999). It is      gamma synchrony can be found in virtually every brain
similarly facilitated by attention (Roelfsema et al. 1997)   region investigated, including some that are unlikely to
and by increases in a dominant stimulus under binoc-         contribute directly to consciousness. Also, it is not yet
ular rivalry even though firing rates may not change          clear whether synchrony in the gamma range vanishes
(Fries et al. 1997, 2001).                                   during early NREM sleep, during anesthesia, or even
   Other evidence has come from EEG studies of phase         during seizures. Human studies are still inconsistent
locking in humans. A recent study compared the neu-          on this point, whereas animal studies show a paradox-
ral correlates of words that were consciously perceived      ical increase in gamma synchrony when rats lose the
with those of masked words that had been processed           righting reflex (thought to correspond more or less to
and semantically decoded but had remained uncon-             the loss of consciousness in humans; see Imas et al.
scious (Melloni et al. 2007). The results showed that        2005a, b). It would seem that there can be synchrony
Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness                                                                     253


without consciousness, though perhaps not conscious-         are organized in a radically different way from human
ness without synchrony, at least in mammalian brains.        brains?
    Finally, there are some difficult conceptual prob-
lems in characterizing synchrony as an essential ingre-         Consciousness as Integrated Information
dient that unifies perceptual states and thereby makes            To address these questions, it would seem that we
them conscious. While many experiences do indeed             need a theoretical approach that tries to establish, at the
involve several different elements and attributes that       fundamental level, what consciousness is, how it can be
are “bound” together into a unified percept, there are        measured, and what requisites a physical system must
many other experiences, equally conscious, that do not       satisfy in order to generate it. The integrated information
seem to require much binding at all: for instance, an        theory of consciousness represents such an approach
experience of pure darkness or of pure blue, or a loud       (Tononi 2004b).
sound that briefly occupies consciousness and has no              According to the theory, the most important prop-
obvious internal structure, would merely seem to re-         erty of consciousness is that is extraordinarily informa-
quire the strong activation of the relevant neurons, with    tive. This is because, whenever you experience a par-
no need for signaling relatedness to other elements,         ticular conscious state, it rules out a huge number of
and thus no need for synchrony. Also, the idea that          alternative experiences. Classically, the reduction of
the NCC of a given conscious experience are given by         uncertainty among a number of alternatives consti-
active neurons bound by synchrony discounts the im-          tutes information. For example, you lie in bed with
portance of inactive ones: information specifying that       eyes open and experience pure darkness and silence.
particular unified experience must be conveyed both           This is one of the simplest experiences you might have,
by which neurons are active and which are not, yet for       one that may not be thought as conveying much in-
inactive neurons there does not seem to be anything          formation. One should realize, however, that the in-
to bind. On the other hand, if most neurons in the           formativeness of what you just experienced lies not in
cortex were to become active hypersynchronously, as          how complicated it is to describe, but in how many
is the case in generalized seizures, they should result in   alternatives were ruled out when you experienced it:
maximal “binding,” but consciousness vanishes rather         you could have experienced any one frame from any of
than become more vivid..                                     innumerable movies, or the smoke and flames of your
                                                             room burning, or any other possible scene, but you did
                                                             not—instead, you experienced darkness and silence.
    Consciousness from a Theoretical                         This means that when you experienced darkness and
              Perspective                                    silence, whether you think or not of what was ruled out
                                                             (and you typically don’t), you actually gained access to
   Progress in the study of the NCC will hopefully           a large amount of information. This point is so simple
lead to a better understanding of what distinguishes         that its importance has been overlooked.
neural structures or processes that are associated with          It is essential to realize, however, that the informa-
consciousness from those that are not. But even if we        tion associated with the occurrence of a conscious state
come closer to this goal, we still need to understand        is integrated information. When you experience a par-
why certain structures and processes have a privileged       ticular conscious state, that conscious state is an inte-
relationship with subjective experience. For example,        grated whole—it cannot be subdivided into compo-
why is it that neurons in thalamocortical circuits are       nents that are experienced independently. For exam-
essential for conscious experience, whereas cerebellar       ple, the conscious experience of the particular phrase
neurons, despite their huge numbers, are not? And            you are reading now cannot be experienced as subdi-
what is wrong with many cortical circuits, including         vided into, say, the conscious experience of how the
those in V1, that makes them unsuitable to yield subjec-     words look independently of the conscious experience
tive experience? Or why is it that consciousness wanes       of how they sound in your mind. Similarly, you cannot
during slow-wave sleep early in the night, despite lev-      experience visual shapes independently of their color,
els of neural firing in the thalamocortical system that       or perceive the left half of the visual field of view inde-
are comparable to those in quiet wakefulness? Other          pendently of the right half.
questions are even more difficult to address in the ab-           Based on these and other considerations, the theory
sence of a theory. For example, is consciousness present     claims that the level of consciousness of a physical system is
in animals that have a nervous system considerably           related to the repertoire of causal states (information) available to
different from ours? And what about computerized             the system as a whole (integration). That is, whenever a sys-
robots or other artifacts that behave intelligently but      tem enters a particular state though causal interactions
254                                                                     Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences

among its elements, it is conscious in proportion to how     that bear some structural resemblance to different parts
many system states it has thereby ruled out, provided        of the brain (Tononi 2004b, 2005). For example, by us-
these are states of the system as a whole, not decom-        ing computer simulations, it is possible to show that
posable into states of causally independent parts. More      high requires networks that conjoin functional spe-
precisely, the theory introduces a measure of integrated     cialization (due to its specialized connectivity, each ele-
information called , quantifying the reduction of un-        ment has a unique functional role within the network)
certainty (i.e., the information) that is generated when a   with functional integration (there are many pathways
system enters a particular state through causal interac-     for interactions among the elements.). In very rough
tions among its parts, above and beyond the informa-         terms, this kind of architecture is characteristic of the
tion that is generated independently within the parts        mammalian thalamo-cortical system: different parts of
themselves (hence integrated information). The parts         the cerebral cortex are specialized for different func-
should be chosen in such a way that they can account         tions, yet a vast network of connections allows these
for as much nonintegrated (independent) information          parts to interact profusely. Indeed, the thalamo-cortical
as possible.                                                 system is precisely the part of the brain which cannot
    If a system has a positive value of (and it is not       be severely impaired without loss of consciousness.
included within a larger subset having higher ) it is            Conversely, is low for systems that are made up of
called a complex. For a complex, and only for a complex,     small, quasi-independent modules. This may be why
it is appropriate to say that when it enters a particular    the cerebellum, despite its large number of neurons,
state, it generates an amount of integrated information      does not contribute much to consciousness: its synaptic
corresponding to . Since integrated information can          organization is such that individual patches of cerebel-
only be generated within a complex and not outside           lar cortex tend to be activated independently of one
its boundaries, consciousness is necessarily subjective,     another, with little interaction between distant patches
private, and related to a single point of view or per-       (Cohen & Yarom 1998; Bower 2002).
spective (Tononi & Edelman 1998). Some properties                Computer simulations also show that units along
of complexes are worth pointing out. A given physical        multiple, segregated incoming or outgoing pathways
system, such as a brain, is likely to contain more than      are not incorporated within the repertoire of the main
one complex, many small ones with low values, and            complex. This may be why neural activity in afferent
perhaps a few large ones. We suspect that in the brain       pathways (perhaps as far as V1), though crucial for
there is at any given time a complex of comparatively        triggering this or that conscious experience, does not
much higher , which we call the main complex. Also,          contribute directly to conscious experience; nor does
a complex can be causally connected to elements that         activity in efferent pathways (perhaps starting with pri-
are not part of it through ports-in and ports-out. In that   mary motor cortex), though it is crucial for reporting
case, elements that are part of the complex contribute       each different experience.
to its conscious experience, while elements that are not         The addition of many parallel cycles also generally
part of it do not, even though they may be connected         does not change the composition of the main complex,
to it and exchange information with it through ports-in      although       values can be altered. Instead, cortical
and ports-out. One should also note that the value           and subcortical cycles or loops implement specialized
of a complex is dependent on both spatial and tem-           subroutines that are capable of influencing the states
poral scales that determine what counts as a state of        of the main thalamocortical complex without joining
the underlying system. In general, the relevant spatial      it. Such informationally insulated cortico-subcortical
and temporal scales are those that jointly maximize          loops could constitute the neural substrates for many
    (Tononi 2004b). In the case of the brain, the spa-       unconscious processes that can affect and be affected
tial elements and time scales that maximize           may    by conscious experience (Baars 1988; Tononi 2004a,
be local collections of neurons such as minicolumns          b), such as those that enable object recognition, lan-
and periods of time comprised between tens and hun-          guage parsing, or translating our vague intentions into
dreds of milliseconds, respectively, though at this stage    the right words. At this stage, however, it is hard to say
it is difficult to adjudicate between minicolumns and         precisely which cortical circuits may be informationally
individual neurons.                                          insulated. Are primary sensory cortices organized like
                                                             massive afferent pathways to a main complex “higher
        Accounting for Neurobiological                       up” in the cortical hierarchy? Is much of prefrontal
                Observations                                 cortex organized like a massive efferent pathway? Do
   Measuring and finding complexes is not easy for            certain cortical areas, such as those belonging to the
realistic systems, but it can be done for simple networks    dorsal visual stream, remain partly segregated from
Tononi koch-08
Tononi koch-08
Tononi koch-08
Tononi koch-08
Tononi koch-08
Tononi koch-08
Tononi koch-08

Contenu connexe

Tendances

Meccanismi neurofisiologici dei disturbi degli stati di coscienza
Meccanismi neurofisiologici dei disturbi degli stati di coscienzaMeccanismi neurofisiologici dei disturbi degli stati di coscienza
Meccanismi neurofisiologici dei disturbi degli stati di coscienzaFondazione Giannino Bassetti
 
Jamie Kleiner Luther Rice Application
Jamie Kleiner Luther Rice ApplicationJamie Kleiner Luther Rice Application
Jamie Kleiner Luther Rice ApplicationJamie Kleiner
 
駒場学部講義2016 人間情報学VI 「意識の神経科学:「盲視」と「統合失調症」を手がかりに」
駒場学部講義2016 人間情報学VI 「意識の神経科学:「盲視」と「統合失調症」を手がかりに」駒場学部講義2016 人間情報学VI 「意識の神経科学:「盲視」と「統合失調症」を手がかりに」
駒場学部講義2016 人間情報学VI 「意識の神経科学:「盲視」と「統合失調症」を手がかりに」Masatoshi Yoshida
 
駒場学部講義2015 総合情報学特論III 「意識の神経科学:「気づき」と「サリエンシー」を手がかりに」
駒場学部講義2015 総合情報学特論III 「意識の神経科学:「気づき」と「サリエンシー」を手がかりに」駒場学部講義2015 総合情報学特論III 「意識の神経科学:「気づき」と「サリエンシー」を手がかりに」
駒場学部講義2015 総合情報学特論III 「意識の神経科学:「気づき」と「サリエンシー」を手がかりに」Masatoshi Yoshida
 
Cerebral function in_coma_vegetative_state_minimal
Cerebral function in_coma_vegetative_state_minimalCerebral function in_coma_vegetative_state_minimal
Cerebral function in_coma_vegetative_state_minimalMarcelaVargas96
 
asp2011_abstracts_modified
asp2011_abstracts_modifiedasp2011_abstracts_modified
asp2011_abstracts_modifiedChris Skaroupka
 
Being and Doing: Activating Neural Networks of Mindful Presence - Rick Hanson...
Being and Doing: Activating Neural Networks of Mindful Presence - Rick Hanson...Being and Doing: Activating Neural Networks of Mindful Presence - Rick Hanson...
Being and Doing: Activating Neural Networks of Mindful Presence - Rick Hanson...Rick Hanson
 
Ryans Psy Ch03 2010
Ryans Psy Ch03 2010Ryans Psy Ch03 2010
Ryans Psy Ch03 2010Cynthia Ryan
 
What is going on in psychiatry when nothing seems to happen
What is going on in psychiatry when nothing seems to happenWhat is going on in psychiatry when nothing seems to happen
What is going on in psychiatry when nothing seems to happenAdonis Sfera, MD
 
総研大講義 「#8 盲視の脳内機構」レジメ
総研大講義 「#8 盲視の脳内機構」レジメ総研大講義 「#8 盲視の脳内機構」レジメ
総研大講義 「#8 盲視の脳内機構」レジメMasatoshi Yoshida
 
Clinical issues: NeuroPhantom psychological theory through explanations adopt...
Clinical issues: NeuroPhantom psychological theory through explanations adopt...Clinical issues: NeuroPhantom psychological theory through explanations adopt...
Clinical issues: NeuroPhantom psychological theory through explanations adopt...Jacob Stotler
 
Consciousness as Integrated Information
Consciousness as Integrated InformationConsciousness as Integrated Information
Consciousness as Integrated InformationShamit Bagchi
 
Unit 5 - CONSCIOUS ANIMAL EXPERIMENTS
Unit 5 - CONSCIOUS ANIMAL EXPERIMENTSUnit 5 - CONSCIOUS ANIMAL EXPERIMENTS
Unit 5 - CONSCIOUS ANIMAL EXPERIMENTSPriyansha Singh
 
Modulation of theta phase sync during a recognition memory task
Modulation of theta phase sync during a recognition memory taskModulation of theta phase sync during a recognition memory task
Modulation of theta phase sync during a recognition memory taskKyongsik Yun
 
Week 2 neural basis of consciousness: introduction to the research methods ts...
Week 2 neural basis of consciousness: introduction to the research methods ts...Week 2 neural basis of consciousness: introduction to the research methods ts...
Week 2 neural basis of consciousness: introduction to the research methods ts...Nao (Naotsugu) Tsuchiya
 
Week 11 neural basis of consciousness : consciousness and integration (1)
Week 11 neural basis of consciousness : consciousness and integration (1)Week 11 neural basis of consciousness : consciousness and integration (1)
Week 11 neural basis of consciousness : consciousness and integration (1)Nao (Naotsugu) Tsuchiya
 
Not-Self in the Brain: Insights from Neuroscience about Not Taking Life Perso...
Not-Self in the Brain: Insights from Neuroscience about Not Taking Life Perso...Not-Self in the Brain: Insights from Neuroscience about Not Taking Life Perso...
Not-Self in the Brain: Insights from Neuroscience about Not Taking Life Perso...Rick Hanson
 

Tendances (20)

Meccanismi neurofisiologici dei disturbi degli stati di coscienza
Meccanismi neurofisiologici dei disturbi degli stati di coscienzaMeccanismi neurofisiologici dei disturbi degli stati di coscienza
Meccanismi neurofisiologici dei disturbi degli stati di coscienza
 
Jamie Kleiner Luther Rice Application
Jamie Kleiner Luther Rice ApplicationJamie Kleiner Luther Rice Application
Jamie Kleiner Luther Rice Application
 
駒場学部講義2016 人間情報学VI 「意識の神経科学:「盲視」と「統合失調症」を手がかりに」
駒場学部講義2016 人間情報学VI 「意識の神経科学:「盲視」と「統合失調症」を手がかりに」駒場学部講義2016 人間情報学VI 「意識の神経科学:「盲視」と「統合失調症」を手がかりに」
駒場学部講義2016 人間情報学VI 「意識の神経科学:「盲視」と「統合失調症」を手がかりに」
 
駒場学部講義2015 総合情報学特論III 「意識の神経科学:「気づき」と「サリエンシー」を手がかりに」
駒場学部講義2015 総合情報学特論III 「意識の神経科学:「気づき」と「サリエンシー」を手がかりに」駒場学部講義2015 総合情報学特論III 「意識の神経科学:「気づき」と「サリエンシー」を手がかりに」
駒場学部講義2015 総合情報学特論III 「意識の神経科学:「気づき」と「サリエンシー」を手がかりに」
 
Cerebral function in_coma_vegetative_state_minimal
Cerebral function in_coma_vegetative_state_minimalCerebral function in_coma_vegetative_state_minimal
Cerebral function in_coma_vegetative_state_minimal
 
asp2011_abstracts_modified
asp2011_abstracts_modifiedasp2011_abstracts_modified
asp2011_abstracts_modified
 
Being and Doing: Activating Neural Networks of Mindful Presence - Rick Hanson...
Being and Doing: Activating Neural Networks of Mindful Presence - Rick Hanson...Being and Doing: Activating Neural Networks of Mindful Presence - Rick Hanson...
Being and Doing: Activating Neural Networks of Mindful Presence - Rick Hanson...
 
The paranormal mind how the study of anomalous experiences and beliefs may ...
The paranormal mind   how the study of anomalous experiences and beliefs may ...The paranormal mind   how the study of anomalous experiences and beliefs may ...
The paranormal mind how the study of anomalous experiences and beliefs may ...
 
Ryans Psy Ch03 2010
Ryans Psy Ch03 2010Ryans Psy Ch03 2010
Ryans Psy Ch03 2010
 
What is going on in psychiatry when nothing seems to happen
What is going on in psychiatry when nothing seems to happenWhat is going on in psychiatry when nothing seems to happen
What is going on in psychiatry when nothing seems to happen
 
The primary function of consciousness in the nervous system
The primary function of consciousness in the nervous systemThe primary function of consciousness in the nervous system
The primary function of consciousness in the nervous system
 
2nd Health Bulletin
2nd Health Bulletin2nd Health Bulletin
2nd Health Bulletin
 
総研大講義 「#8 盲視の脳内機構」レジメ
総研大講義 「#8 盲視の脳内機構」レジメ総研大講義 「#8 盲視の脳内機構」レジメ
総研大講義 「#8 盲視の脳内機構」レジメ
 
Clinical issues: NeuroPhantom psychological theory through explanations adopt...
Clinical issues: NeuroPhantom psychological theory through explanations adopt...Clinical issues: NeuroPhantom psychological theory through explanations adopt...
Clinical issues: NeuroPhantom psychological theory through explanations adopt...
 
Consciousness as Integrated Information
Consciousness as Integrated InformationConsciousness as Integrated Information
Consciousness as Integrated Information
 
Unit 5 - CONSCIOUS ANIMAL EXPERIMENTS
Unit 5 - CONSCIOUS ANIMAL EXPERIMENTSUnit 5 - CONSCIOUS ANIMAL EXPERIMENTS
Unit 5 - CONSCIOUS ANIMAL EXPERIMENTS
 
Modulation of theta phase sync during a recognition memory task
Modulation of theta phase sync during a recognition memory taskModulation of theta phase sync during a recognition memory task
Modulation of theta phase sync during a recognition memory task
 
Week 2 neural basis of consciousness: introduction to the research methods ts...
Week 2 neural basis of consciousness: introduction to the research methods ts...Week 2 neural basis of consciousness: introduction to the research methods ts...
Week 2 neural basis of consciousness: introduction to the research methods ts...
 
Week 11 neural basis of consciousness : consciousness and integration (1)
Week 11 neural basis of consciousness : consciousness and integration (1)Week 11 neural basis of consciousness : consciousness and integration (1)
Week 11 neural basis of consciousness : consciousness and integration (1)
 
Not-Self in the Brain: Insights from Neuroscience about Not Taking Life Perso...
Not-Self in the Brain: Insights from Neuroscience about Not Taking Life Perso...Not-Self in the Brain: Insights from Neuroscience about Not Taking Life Perso...
Not-Self in the Brain: Insights from Neuroscience about Not Taking Life Perso...
 

En vedette

Как сделать научную публикацию в престижном западном издательстве?
Как сделать научную публикацию в престижном западном издательстве?Как сделать научную публикацию в престижном западном издательстве?
Как сделать научную публикацию в престижном западном издательстве?Margarita Saydalieva
 
Q3L07 - The Brain (documentary questions)
Q3L07 - The Brain (documentary questions)Q3L07 - The Brain (documentary questions)
Q3L07 - The Brain (documentary questions)Dickson College
 
Demonstration Of Presentation Structure
Demonstration Of Presentation StructureDemonstration Of Presentation Structure
Demonstration Of Presentation StructureOlivia Mitchell
 
Useful phrases for academic writing
Useful phrases for academic writingUseful phrases for academic writing
Useful phrases for academic writingEssayAcademy
 
How to give a scientific research presentation
How to give a scientific research presentationHow to give a scientific research presentation
How to give a scientific research presentationKhon Kaen University
 
Fifteen thousand useful phrases
Fifteen thousand useful phrasesFifteen thousand useful phrases
Fifteen thousand useful phrasesBeeLast
 
What is a Scientific Presentation ?
What is a Scientific Presentation ?What is a Scientific Presentation ?
What is a Scientific Presentation ?Steve Johnson
 
Consciousness PowerPoint
Consciousness PowerPointConsciousness PowerPoint
Consciousness PowerPointKRyder
 
How to structure a presentation a guide with examples
How to structure a presentation a guide with examplesHow to structure a presentation a guide with examples
How to structure a presentation a guide with examplescoolsimo
 
What is consciousness?
What is consciousness?What is consciousness?
What is consciousness?DMLab
 
Illustrated everyday expressions_with_stories_1
Illustrated everyday expressions_with_stories_1Illustrated everyday expressions_with_stories_1
Illustrated everyday expressions_with_stories_1Leon_Panetta
 
Useful phrases for speaking
Useful phrases for speakingUseful phrases for speaking
Useful phrases for speakingandydei
 

En vedette (15)

Как сделать научную публикацию в престижном западном издательстве?
Как сделать научную публикацию в престижном западном издательстве?Как сделать научную публикацию в престижном западном издательстве?
Как сделать научную публикацию в престижном западном издательстве?
 
16 apr 27 tucson iit talk
16 apr 27 tucson iit talk16 apr 27 tucson iit talk
16 apr 27 tucson iit talk
 
Q3L07 - The Brain (documentary questions)
Q3L07 - The Brain (documentary questions)Q3L07 - The Brain (documentary questions)
Q3L07 - The Brain (documentary questions)
 
Demonstration Of Presentation Structure
Demonstration Of Presentation StructureDemonstration Of Presentation Structure
Demonstration Of Presentation Structure
 
Information integration
Information integrationInformation integration
Information integration
 
Useful phrases for academic writing
Useful phrases for academic writingUseful phrases for academic writing
Useful phrases for academic writing
 
How to give a scientific research presentation
How to give a scientific research presentationHow to give a scientific research presentation
How to give a scientific research presentation
 
Fifteen thousand useful phrases
Fifteen thousand useful phrasesFifteen thousand useful phrases
Fifteen thousand useful phrases
 
What is a Scientific Presentation ?
What is a Scientific Presentation ?What is a Scientific Presentation ?
What is a Scientific Presentation ?
 
Talk talk talk 1
Talk talk talk 1Talk talk talk 1
Talk talk talk 1
 
Consciousness PowerPoint
Consciousness PowerPointConsciousness PowerPoint
Consciousness PowerPoint
 
How to structure a presentation a guide with examples
How to structure a presentation a guide with examplesHow to structure a presentation a guide with examples
How to structure a presentation a guide with examples
 
What is consciousness?
What is consciousness?What is consciousness?
What is consciousness?
 
Illustrated everyday expressions_with_stories_1
Illustrated everyday expressions_with_stories_1Illustrated everyday expressions_with_stories_1
Illustrated everyday expressions_with_stories_1
 
Useful phrases for speaking
Useful phrases for speakingUseful phrases for speaking
Useful phrases for speaking
 

Similaire à Tononi koch-08

Consciousness & neuroscience francis crick & christof koch
Consciousness & neuroscience francis crick & christof kochConsciousness & neuroscience francis crick & christof koch
Consciousness & neuroscience francis crick & christof kochnjqtpie86
 
Introduction of Neuropsychology (History and branches)
Introduction of Neuropsychology (History and branches)Introduction of Neuropsychology (History and branches)
Introduction of Neuropsychology (History and branches)Home
 
PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out
  PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out  PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out
PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Outajoy21
 
PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out.docx
  PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out.docx  PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out.docx
PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out.docxShiraPrater50
 
BRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docx
BRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docxBRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docx
BRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docxjackiewalcutt
 
Consciousness in the universe a review of the ‘orch or’ theory by hameroff an...
Consciousness in the universe a review of the ‘orch or’ theory by hameroff an...Consciousness in the universe a review of the ‘orch or’ theory by hameroff an...
Consciousness in the universe a review of the ‘orch or’ theory by hameroff an...Julio Banks
 
The_Body_Magnetic_The_physical_source_of.pdf
The_Body_Magnetic_The_physical_source_of.pdfThe_Body_Magnetic_The_physical_source_of.pdf
The_Body_Magnetic_The_physical_source_of.pdfCarlosMendez823378
 
Dr Van Der Kolk ~ Clinical implications of neuroscience research in PTSD
Dr Van Der Kolk ~ Clinical implications of neuroscience research in PTSDDr Van Der Kolk ~ Clinical implications of neuroscience research in PTSD
Dr Van Der Kolk ~ Clinical implications of neuroscience research in PTSDAmerican Fathers Liberation Army
 
Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology a new theory with respect to m...
Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology a new theory with respect to m...Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology a new theory with respect to m...
Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology a new theory with respect to m...Elsa von Licy
 
Dr Heidi Haavik Melbourne Presentation
Dr Heidi Haavik Melbourne PresentationDr Heidi Haavik Melbourne Presentation
Dr Heidi Haavik Melbourne Presentationheidihaavik
 
Premotor Cortex Argumentative Analysis
Premotor Cortex Argumentative AnalysisPremotor Cortex Argumentative Analysis
Premotor Cortex Argumentative AnalysisAmanda Hengel
 
Ap Psychology Case Study
Ap Psychology Case StudyAp Psychology Case Study
Ap Psychology Case StudyKate Loge
 

Similaire à Tononi koch-08 (20)

Minimal neuroanatomy for a conscious brain
Minimal neuroanatomy for a conscious brainMinimal neuroanatomy for a conscious brain
Minimal neuroanatomy for a conscious brain
 
Consciousness & neuroscience francis crick & christof koch
Consciousness & neuroscience francis crick & christof kochConsciousness & neuroscience francis crick & christof koch
Consciousness & neuroscience francis crick & christof koch
 
Introduction of Neuropsychology (History and branches)
Introduction of Neuropsychology (History and branches)Introduction of Neuropsychology (History and branches)
Introduction of Neuropsychology (History and branches)
 
Developing consciousness fetal anesthesia and analgesia
Developing consciousness fetal anesthesia and analgesiaDeveloping consciousness fetal anesthesia and analgesia
Developing consciousness fetal anesthesia and analgesia
 
Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience
Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscienceConsciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience
Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience
 
PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out
  PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out  PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out
PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out
 
PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out.docx
  PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out.docx  PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out.docx
PSY 1010, General Psychology 1 Course Learning Out.docx
 
BRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docx
BRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docxBRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docx
BRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docx
 
Consciousness in the universe a review of the ‘orch or’ theory by hameroff an...
Consciousness in the universe a review of the ‘orch or’ theory by hameroff an...Consciousness in the universe a review of the ‘orch or’ theory by hameroff an...
Consciousness in the universe a review of the ‘orch or’ theory by hameroff an...
 
The_Body_Magnetic_The_physical_source_of.pdf
The_Body_Magnetic_The_physical_source_of.pdfThe_Body_Magnetic_The_physical_source_of.pdf
The_Body_Magnetic_The_physical_source_of.pdf
 
Dr Van Der Kolk ~ Clinical implications of neuroscience research in PTSD
Dr Van Der Kolk ~ Clinical implications of neuroscience research in PTSDDr Van Der Kolk ~ Clinical implications of neuroscience research in PTSD
Dr Van Der Kolk ~ Clinical implications of neuroscience research in PTSD
 
Myelination Essay
Myelination EssayMyelination Essay
Myelination Essay
 
Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology a new theory with respect to m...
Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology a new theory with respect to m...Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology a new theory with respect to m...
Quantum physics in neuroscience and psychology a new theory with respect to m...
 
Dr Heidi Haavik Melbourne Presentation
Dr Heidi Haavik Melbourne PresentationDr Heidi Haavik Melbourne Presentation
Dr Heidi Haavik Melbourne Presentation
 
Premotor Cortex Argumentative Analysis
Premotor Cortex Argumentative AnalysisPremotor Cortex Argumentative Analysis
Premotor Cortex Argumentative Analysis
 
Cognitive Psychology Essay
Cognitive Psychology EssayCognitive Psychology Essay
Cognitive Psychology Essay
 
Ap Psychology Case Study
Ap Psychology Case StudyAp Psychology Case Study
Ap Psychology Case Study
 
Psychology Ppt
Psychology PptPsychology Ppt
Psychology Ppt
 
L.O.V.E.
L.O.V.E.L.O.V.E.
L.O.V.E.
 
Councious.pptx
Councious.pptxCouncious.pptx
Councious.pptx
 

Tononi koch-08

  • 1. The Neural Correlates of Consciousness An Update GIULIO TONONIa AND CHRISTOF KOCHb a Department of Psychiatry, University of Wisconsin, Madison, Wisconsin, USA b Division of Biology and the Division of Engineering and Applied Science, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, California, USA This review examines recent advances in the study of brain correlates of consciousness. First, we briefly discuss some useful distinctions between consciousness and other brain functions. We then examine what has been learned by studying global changes in the level of consciousness, such as sleep, anesthesia, and seizures. Next we consider some of the most common paradigms used to study the neural correlates for specific conscious percepts and examine what recent findings say about the role of different brain regions in giving rise to consciousness for that percept. Then we discuss dynamic aspects of neural activity, such as sustained versus phasic activity, feedforward versus reentrant activity, and the role of neural synchronization. Finally, we briefly consider how a theoretical analysis of the fundamental properties of consciousness can usefully complement neurobiological studies. Key words: consciousness; brain; information Introduction consciousness is, how it can be generated by a physi- cal system, and how it can be measured and then to There are several strategies by which scientists can test the predictions of the theory against data from approach the relationship between the brain and con- neuroscience (Tononi 2004b). sciousness. One is to wait and hope that, once we know This review focuses on recent advances in the study all there is to know about neuroanatomy and neuro- of the NCC. First, we briefly discuss some useful dis- physiology (or maybe when we can model in detail the tinctions between consciousness and other brain func- working of the entire brain; Markram 2006), the an- tions. We then examine what has been learned about swer will somehow pop out. A more practical approach the NCC by studying global changes in the level of con- is to use the tools of neuroscience that are available sciousness, such as sleep, anesthesia, and generalized now to shed light on the neural structures and activ- seizures. Next, we consider some of the most com- ity patterns that underlie consciousness. For example, mon paradigms used to study the NCC for specific one can examine how brain activity changes when, conscious percepts and examine what recent findings everything else being as equal as possible, a stimulus say about the role of different brain regions in giving is experienced or not. In this way, one can attempt to rise to consciousness for that percept. Finally, we dis- identify, more and more precisely, the neural correlates cuss the relation to the NCC of dynamic aspects of of consciousness (NCC), defined as the minimal neuronal neural activity, such as sustained versus phasic activity, mechanisms jointly sufficient for any one specific conscious percept feedforward versus reentrant activity, and the role of (Koch 2003). A complementary strategy is to consider neural synchronization. We end with a few remarks on conditions in which consciousness is globally dimin- the importance of a combined theoretical and neuro- ished, such as deep sleep or anesthesia, and ask what biological approach. has changed in the brain. Finally, another approach is to develop a theoretical framework that clarifies what Consciousness and Other Brain Functions Address for correspondence: Christof Koch, Division of Biology and the Division of Engineering and Applied Science, 216-76, California Institute Many suggestions have been ventured in the hope of of Technology, Pasadena, CA 91125. Fax: +1-626-796-8876. alleviating the puzzle of subjective experience. Perhaps koch@klab.caltech.edu consciousness emerges somehow when an organism is Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 1124: 239–261 (2008). C 2008 New York Academy of Sciences. doi: 10.1196/annals.1440.004 239
  • 2. 240 Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences immersed in some complex sensorimotor loop that in- et al. 1998). Patients with the locked-in syndrome can cludes the environment. Another common idea is that be almost completely paralyzed, and yet they are just consciousness may somehow arise when one part of as conscious as healthy subjects (Laureys et al. 2005) the brain, acting as the “subject” (typically the front), and can compose eloquent accounts of their condition looks upon another part as its “object” (typically the (Bauby 1997). A transient form of paralysis is one of the back), and evaluates or reflects upon its activity. It is of- characteristic features of narcolepsy. Severe cataleptic ten thought that in the end consciousness may reduce attacks can last for minutes and leave the patient col- to attention and its brain mechanisms, since we are lapsed on the floor, utterly unable to move or to sig- usually conscious of what we attend. Much could be nal, but fully aware of her surroundings (Guilleminault said about each of these suggestions. Here, we briefly 1976; Siegel 2000). Or consider the Californian drug consider some recent results (and some very old evi- addicts known as the frozen addicts who acquired some of dence) indicating that consciousness—in the sense of the symptoms of severe, late-stage Parkinson’s disease, having an experience—does not require sensorimotor fully conscious, yet unable to move or speak (Langston loops involving the body and the world, does not re- & Palfreman 1995). All six had previously taken syn- quire self-reflection (or language), and does not reduce thetic heroin tainted with MPTP, which selectively and to attention. permanently destroyed dopamine-producing neurons in their basal ganglia. Thus, consciousness here and Consciousness and Sensory Input/Motor now seems to depend on what certain parts of the brain Output are doing, without requiring any obligatory interaction We are usually conscious of what goes on around with the environment or the body. us, and occasionally of what goes on within our body. So it is only natural to think that consciousness may Consciousness and Self-Reflection be tightly linked to the ongoing interaction we main- Consciousness is usually evaluated by verbal reports, tain with the world and the body. However, there are and questions about consciousness (“Did you see any- many examples to the contrary. We are conscious of thing on the screen?”) are answered by “looking in- our thoughts, which do not seem to correspond to any- side” retrospectively and reporting what one has just thing out there; we can also imagine things that are experienced. So it is perhaps natural to suggest that not out there. When we do so, sensory areas can be consciousness may arise through the ability to reflect activated from the inside (Kosslyn et al. 2001), though on our own perceptions: our brain would form a scene there are some differences (Amedi et al. 2005). Also, of what it sees, but we would become conscious of it— stimulus-independent consciousness is associated with experience it subjectively—only when we, as a subject its own patterns of activation within cortex and tha- of experience, watch that scene from the inside. This lamus (Mason et al. 2007). During dreams, we are suggestion is often framed in a neurobiological context virtually disconnected from the environment (Hobson by assuming that patterns of activity corresponding et al. 2000)—hardly anything of what happens around to “unconscious” or “subconscious” percepts form in us enters consciousness, and our muscles are paralyzed posterior regions of the cerebral cortex involved in the (except for eye muscles and diaphragm). Nevertheless, categorization/association of sensory stimuli. These we are vividly conscious: all that seems to matter is percepts then become conscious when mainly ante- that the thalamocortical system continues to function rior prefrontal and cingulate regions involved in self- more or less as in wakefulness, as shown by unit record- representations interact with posterior cortex, perhaps ing, EEG, and neuroimaging studies performed dur- by reading in signals through forward connections and ing rapid eye movement (REM) sleep, when dreams selectively amplifying them through back connections are most intense (Maquet et al. 1996). Interestingly, (more on this later). certain regions of the thalamocortical systems, such There is of course no doubt that the brain catego- as dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, are deactivated in rizes its own patterns of activity in the sense that neu- REM sleep, which likely accounts for some peculiari- rons respond mainly to the activity of other neurons, ties of dreaming experiences, such as the reduction of so the brain is constantly “looking at itself.” However, voluntary control. this is not necessarily in terms of a “subject” (the front) Neurological evidence also indicates that neither looking at an “object” represented in sensory cortices sensory inputs nor motor outputs are needed to gener- (the back). Leaving aside the mystery of why reflecting ate consciousness. For instance, retinally blind people on something should make it conscious, this scenario can both imagine and dream visually if they become is made less plausible by a common observation: when blind after 6–7 years of age or so (Hollins 1985; Buchel we become absorbed in some intense perceptual task,
  • 3. Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness 241 for example watching an engrossing movie, playing a and social setting. Although displaying many of the fast-paced video game, or rushing through the woods typical frontal lobe behavioral disturbances, he never at high speed, we are vividly conscious—we are im- complained of loss of sensory perception, nor did he mersed in the rapid flow of experience—without any show visual or other deficits (Mataro et al. 2001). An- need for reflection or introspection. Often, we become other case is that of a 27-year-old woman with mas- so immersed in such flow that we may lose the sense sive bilateral prefrontal damage of unclear etiology of self, the inner voice. Perhaps the habit of thinking (Markowitsch & Kessler 2000). While manifesting about consciousness has distracted the scholars who grossly deficient scores in frontal lobe sensitive tests, write upon such matters to devalue the unreflective she showed no abnormal perceptual abilities (that is nature of much of experience. not to say that such patients do not suffer from subtle A recent neuroimaging study by Malach and col- visual deficits; Barcelo et al. 2000). laborators (Hasson et al. 2004) throws some inter- esting light on these old observations. Subjects were Consciousness and Attention scanned with fMRI in three conditions. In the slow Consciousness and attention have resisted clear and categorization task, subjects were asked to catego- compelling definitions. Few would dispute that the re- rize pictures into animal/no-animal categories. Dur- lationship between the two is an intimate one. When ing the introspective task, subjects viewed the images subjects pay attention to an object, they become con- and then introspected about their emotional response scious of its various attributes; when the focus of at- (strong/neutral). Finally, the fast categorization task tention shifts away, the object fades from conscious- was identical to the “slow” condition but at triple ness. Indeed, more than a century of research efforts the stimulation rate. Thus, “slow” and “introspection” have quantified the ample benefits accrued to attended conditions were identical in terms of sensory stimuli and consciously perceived events (Pashler 1998; Braun and motor output but differed in the cognitive task. et al. 2001). This has prompted many to posit that the On the other hand, “slow” and “rapid” conditions two processes are inextricably interwoven, if not iden- were similar in the cognitive task but differed in the tical (Posner 1994; Merikle & Joordens 1997; Chun & sensorimotor processing and attentional loads. Behav- Wolfe 2000; O’Regan & Noe 2000). Others, however, ioral measurements confirmed that self-awareness was going back to the 19th century, have argued that atten- high during the introspection task, and virtually abol- tion and consciousness are distinct phenomena, with ished during rapid categorization. The neuroimaging distinct functions and neuronal mechanisms (Iwasaki results were clear: during introspection there was an 1993; Hardcastle 1997; Lamme 2003; Baars 2005; activation of prefrontal regions, whereas sensory cor- Block 2005; Dehaene et al. 2006; Koch & Tsuchiya tex was strongly activated during rapid categorization. 2007). Recent psychophysical and neurophysiological Crucially, during introspection self-related cortex was evidence argues in favor of a dissociation between selec- deactivated below the rest condition. This deactiva- tive attention and consciousness, suggesting that events tion of prefrontal regions was thus the neural corre- or objects can be attended to without being consciously late of “losing oneself ” in the task. To the extent that perceived. Conversely, an event or object can be con- these prefrontal regions were indeed involved in self- sciously perceived in the near absence of top-down representation, these findings suggest that their activa- attentional processing. tion is not necessary for the emergence of perceptual consciousness, but only to reflect upon it and report it Attention without Consciousness to others. Indeed, it appears that self-related activity Consider that subjects can attend to a location for is actually shut off during highly demanding sensory many seconds and yet fail to see one or more attributes tasks. of an object at that location. In lateral masking (visual Lesion studies also seem to support the notion that crowding), the orientation of a peripherally presented consciousness does not require prefrontal cortex and, grating is hidden from conscious sight but remains by inference, the functions it performs. Though pa- sufficiently potent to induce an orientation-dependent tients with widespread, bilateral damage to prefrontal aftereffect (He et al. 1996) Montaser-Kouhsari and cortex are rare, two recent clinical studies provide Rajimehr (2004) showed that an aftereffect induced some intriguing evidence. A man who, at the age by an invisible illusory contour required focal atten- of 21, had fallen on an iron spike that completely tion, even though the object at the center of attention penetrated through both of his frontal lobes, never- was invisible. Naccache and colleagues (2002) elicited theless went on to live a stable life—marrying and priming for invisible words (suppressed by a combi- raising two children—in an appropriate professional nation of forward and backward masking) but only if
  • 4. 242 Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences the subject was attending to the invisible prime-target (or a vehicle), while being unable to distinguish a red- pair; without attention, the same word failed to elicit green bisected disk from a green-red one (Li et al. priming. That is, the subject needs to attend to the 2002). Likewise, subjects can tell male from female masked stimulus for priming to occur, but the actual faces or even distinguish a famous from a nonfamous stimulus is not seen (with an associated d = 0). In face (Reddy et al. 2004; Reddy & Koch 2006) but are another experiment, male/female nudes attracted at- frustrated by tasks that are computationally much sim- tention and induced involuntary eye movements when pler (e.g., discriminating a rotated letter “L” from a they were rendered completely invisible by continuous rotated “T”). This is quite remarkable. Thus, while we flash suppression (Jiang et al. 2006). When subjects had cannot be sure that observers do not deploy some lim- to discriminate the location of the masked nude from ited amount of top-down attention in these dual-task the location of a masked shuffled nude, they were at experiments that require training and concentration chance; without the intraocular masking, the images (i.e., high arousal), it remains true that subjects can are clearly visible. fMRI evidence confirms attentional perform certain discriminations but not others in the modulation of invisible images in primary visual cor- near absence of top-down attention. And they are not tex (Bahrami et al. 2007). In conclusion, attentional guessing. They can be quite confident of their choices selection does not necessarily engender phenomenal and “see,” albeit often indistinctly, what they can sensations, although it may often do so. discriminate. The existence of such dissociations—attention Consciousness in the Absence of Attention without consciousness and consciousness without When focusing intensely on one event, the world attention—should not be surprising when considering is not reduced to a tunnel, with everything outside their different functions. Attention is a set of mecha- the focus of attention gone: we are always aware of nisms whereby the brain selects a subset of the incom- some aspects of the world surrounding us, such as its ing sensory information for higher level processing, gist. Indeed, gist is immune from inattentional blind- while the nonattended portions of the input are ana- ness (Mack & Rock 1998)—when a photograph cover- lyzed at a lower band width. For example, in primates, ing the entire background is briefly and unexpectedly about one million fibers leave each eye and carry on flashed onto the screen, subjects can accurately report the order of one megabyte per second of raw infor- a summary of its content. In the 30 ms necessary to ap- mation. One way to deal with this deluge of data is to prehend the gist of a scene, top-down attention cannot select a small fraction and process this reduced input in play much of a role (because gist is a property asso- real time, while the nonattended data suffer from be- ciated with the entire image, any process that locally nign neglect. Attention can be directed by bottom-up, enhances features is going to be of limited use). exogenous cues or by top-down endogenous features Or take the perception of a single object (say a bar) in and can be applied to a spatially restricted part of the an otherwise empty display, a nonecological but com- image (focal, spotlight of attention), an attribute (e.g., mon arrangement in many animal and human experi- all red objects), or to an entire object. By contrast, con- ments. Here, what function would top-down, selective sciousness appears to be involved in providing a kind attention need to perform without any competing item of “executive summary” of the current situation that in or around fixation? Indeed, the most popular neu- is useful for decision making, planning, and learning ronal model of attention, biased competition (Desimone (Baars). & Duncan 1995), predicts that in the absence of com- petition, no or little attentional enhancement occurs, yet we are perfectly aware of the object and its back- Changes in the Level of Consciousness ground. In a dual-task paradigms, the subject’s attention is In neurology, a distinction is traditionally made be- drawn to a demanding central task, while at the same tween the level of consciousness and the content of time a secondary stimulus is flashed somewhere in the consciousness. When you fall asleep, for example, the periphery. Using the identical retinal layout, the sub- level of consciousness decreases to the point that you ject either performs the central task, the peripheral become virtually unconscious—the degree to which task, or both simultaneously (Sperling & Dosher 1986; you are conscious (of anything) becomes progressively Braun & Sagi 1990; Braun & Julesz 1998). With fo- less and less. The content of consciousness, instead, cal attention busy at the center, the subject can still refers to the particular experience you’re having at any distinguish a natural scene containing an animal (or given time, for the same level of consciousness. It is use- a vehicle) from one that does not include an animal ful to maintain this distinction when considering the
  • 5. Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness 243 NCC, and begin by considering changes in the level of An intriguing possibility is that changes in the level consciousness. of consciousness during sleep may be related to the de- gree of bistability of thalamocortical networks (Tononi Sleep 2004b; Massimini et al. 2007). In a recent study, tran- Sleep offers a commonplace, daily demonstration scranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) was used in con- that the level of consciousness can change dramati- junction with high-density EEG to record cortical cally. In the laboratory, a subject is awakened during evoked responses to direct stimulation in waking and different stages of sleep and asked to report “anything sleep (Massimini et al. 2005; Massimini et al. 2007). that was going through your mind just before waking During wakefulness, TMS induced a sustained re- up.” What is most noteworthy for the present pur- sponse made of rapidly changing patterns of activity poses is that a number of awakenings from non-REM that persisted until 300 ms and involved the sequen- (NREM) sleep, especially early in the night when EEG tial activation of specific brain areas, depending on slow waves are prevalent, can yield no report what- the precise site of stimulation. During early NREM soever. Thus, early slow-wave sleep is the only phase sleep, however, the brain response to TMS changed of adult life during which healthy human subjects may markedly. When applied to lateral cortical regions, deny that they were experiencing anything at all. When the activity evoked by TMS remained localized to the present, reports from NREM sleep early in the night site of stimulation, without activating connected brain are often short and thought-like. However, especially regions, and lasted for less than 150 ms (Massimini later in the night, reports from NREM sleep can be et al. 2005). This finding indicates that during early longer, more hallucinatory and, generally speaking, NREM sleep, when the level of consciousness is re- more dream-like. On the other hand, awakenings dur- duced, effective connectivity among cortical regions ing REM sleep almost always yield dreams—vivid con- breaks down, implying a corresponding breakdown of scious experiences, sometimes organized within a com- cortical integration. Computer simulations suggest that plex narrative structure (Hobson et al. 2000; Hobson this breakdown of effective connectivity may be due to & Pace-Schott 2002). the induction of a local down state (Esser & Tononi, in What are the processes underlying the fading of the preparation). When applied over centromedian pari- level of consciousness during early slow-wave sleep? etal regions, each TMS pulse triggered a stereotypical Though metabolic rates decrease in many cortical ar- response implying the induction of a global down state: eas, especially frontal and parietal areas, the thalam- a full-fledged, high-amplitude slow wave (Massimini et ocortical system is far from shutting down. Instead, al. 2007) that closely resembled spontaneous ones and triggered by a decrease in acetylcholine and other that traveled through much of the cortex (Massimini modulators, cortical and thalamic neurons undergo et al. 2004). Such stereotypical responses could be in- slow oscillations (1 Hz or less) between an up and duced even when, for the preceding seconds, there a down state (Steriade et al. 2001). During the up were no slow waves in the spontaneous EEG, indicat- state, cortical cells remain depolarized at waking levels ing that perturbations can reveal the potential bista- for around a second and fire at waking rates, often bility of a system irrespective of its observed state. Al- in the gamma range (Destexhe et al. 2007). How- together, these TMS–EEG measurements suggest that ever, the up state of NREM sleep is not stable as the sleeping brain, despite being active and reactive, in wakefulness and REM sleep, but it is inherently becomes inherently bistable: it either breaks down in bistable. The longer neurons remain depolarized, the causally independent modules or bursts into a global, more likely they become to precipitate into a hyper- stereotypical response. By contrast, during REM sleep polarized down state—a complete cessation of synap- late in the night, when dreams become long and vivid tic activity that can last for a tenth of a second or and consciousness returns to levels close to those of more—after which they revert to another up state. wakefulness, the responses to TMS also recover and The transition from up to down states appears to be come to resemble more closely those observed dur- due to depolarization-dependent potassium currents ing wakefulness: evoked patterns of activity become and to short-term synaptic depression, both of which more complex and spatially differentiated, although increase with the amount of prior activation (Steri- some late components are still missing (Massimini & ade 2003). The slow oscillation is found in virtually Tononi, unpublished). every cortical neuron and is synchronized across the cortical mantle by cortico-cortical connections, which Anesthesia is why the EEG records high-voltage, low-frequency The most common among exogenous manip- waves. ulations of the level of consciousness is general
  • 6. 244 Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences anesthesia. Anesthetics come in two main classes: intra- of action of several anesthetics is the posterior cingu- venous agents used for induction, such as propofol and late/medial parietal cortical areas, as well as the me- ketamine, which are generally administered together dial basal forebrain). However, both PET and fMRI with sedatives such as midazolam and dexmedeto- signals mostly reflect synaptic activity rather than cel- midine; and inhaled agents, such as isoflurane, lular firing, and the thalamus receives a massive in- sevoflurane, and desflurane or the gases xenon and nervation from cortex. Moreover, the relative reduc- nitrous oxide. The doses of inhaled anesthetics are tion in thalamic activity occurs on a background of a usually referred to their minimum alveolar concen- marked decrease in global metabolism (30–60%) that tration (MAC): a MAC value of 1 is the dose that involves many cortical regions. Thus, thalamic activity prevents movement in 50% of subjects in response as recorded by neuroimaging may represent an es- to a painful surgical stimulation. At low MAC values pecially sensitive, localized readout of the extent of (0.1–0.2) anesthetics produce amnesia, first explicit and widespread cortical deactivation, rather than the final then implicit. Frequently there are distortions of time common pathway of unconsciousness (Ori et al. 1986). perception, such as slowing down and fragmentation, In fact, spontaneous thalamic firing in animal models and a feeling of disconnection from the environment. of anesthesia is mostly driven by corticothalamic feed- Also, at low MAC values anesthetics produce increas- back (Vahle-Hinz et al. 2007), and the metabolic effects ing sleepiness and make arousal progressively more dif- of enflurane on the thalamus can be abolished by an ficult, suggesting that to some extent they can mimic ipsilateral cortical ablation (Nakakimura et al. 1988), neurophysiological events underlying sleep. At around suggesting that the switch in thalamic unit activity is 0.3 MAC people experience a decrease in the level driven primarily through a reduction in afferent cor- of consciousness, also described as a “shrinking” in ticothalamic feedback more than by a direct effect of the field of consciousness, as if they were kept on the anesthesia on thalamic neurons. Recently, thalamic ac- verge of falling asleep. MAC-awake, usually around tivity was recorded using depth electrodes in a patient 0.3–0.4 MAC, is the point at which response to ver- undergoing anesthesia for the implant of a deep brain bal command is lost in 50% of patients and is con- stimulator (Velly et al. 2007). With either propofol or sidered the point at which consciousness is lost (LOC). sevoflurane, when the patient lost consciousness, the The transition to unconsciousness (LOC) appears to be cortical EEG changed dramatically. However, there rather brusque, not unlike the collapse of muscle tone was little change in the thalamic EEG until almost that usually accompanies it, suggesting that neural pro- 10 min later. This result implies that the deactivation cesses underlying consciousness change in a nonlinear of cortex alone is sufficient for loss of consciousness, manner. At concentrations above LOC, movements and conversely that thalamic activity alone is insuffi- are still possible, especially partially coordinated re- cient to maintain it. sponses to painful stimuli, suggesting that some degree These findings do not imply that the thalamus is of “unconscious” processing is still possible. Complete irrelevant, but rather suggest that its effects on con- unresponsiveness is usually obtained just above MAC sciousness are largely accounted for by its effects on of 1.0. cortical circuits, most notably by providing a tonic fa- At the cellular level, many anesthetics have mixed ef- cilitatory action that can help to restore consciousness, fects, but the overall result is a decrease in neuronal ex- or cause its collapse when it fails. A dramatic demon- citability by either increasing inhibition or decreasing stration is provided by a recent study, where rats kept excitation. Most anesthetics act by enhancing GABA under anesthetic concentration of sevoflurane could be inhibition or by hyperpolarizing cells through an in- awakened by a minute injection of nicotinic agents in crease of potassium-leak currents. They can also inter- an intralaminar thalamic nucleus (Alkire et al. 2007). fere with glutamatergic transmission and antagonize Conversely, GABA agonists infused into the same side acetylcholine at nicotinic receptors (Campagna et al. caused an immediate loss of consciousness (Miller et al. 2003; Franks 2006). But what are critical circuits me- 1989; Miller & Ferrendelli 1990) (though nicotinic an- diating the LOC induced by anesthetics? tagonists did not). A considerable number of neuroimaging studies in humans have recently shed some light on this issue Coma and Vegetative States (Alkire & Miller 2005). The most consistent effects While consciousness may nearly fade during cer- produced by most anesthetics at LOC is a reduction tain phases of sleep and be kept at very low lev- of thalamic metabolism and blood flow, suggesting the els for a prescribed period during general anesthe- possibility that the thalamus may serve as a conscious- sia, coma and vegetative states are characterized by ness switch (Alkire et al. 2000). (Another common site a loss of consciousness that is hard or impossible to
  • 7. Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness 245 reverse. Coma—an enduring sleep-like state of immo- cortices (Laureys et al. 2000a). A recent study by Niko bility with eyes closed from which the patient cannot be Schiff and colleagues shows the role of the thalamus aroused—represents the paradigmatic form of patho- even more dramatically: bilateral deep brain electri- logical loss of consciousness. Typically, coma is caused cal stimulation of the central thalamus restored a de- by a suppression of thalamocortical function by drugs, gree of behavioral responsiveness in a patient who had toxins, or internal metabolic derangements. Other remained in a minimally conscious state for 6 years causes of coma are head trauma, strokes, or hypoxia following brain trauma (Schiff et al. 2007). due to heart failure, which again cause widespread de- In vegetative states, brain metabolism is globally re- struction of thalamocortical circuits. Smaller lesions of duced by 50 to 60%, most notably in regions such as the the reticular activating system can also cause uncon- posterior cingulate cortex and the precuneus (Laureys sciousness, presumably by deactivating the thalamo- et al. 2004; Schiff 2006a). These are also the areas that cortical system indirectly. reactivate most reliably if a patient regains conscious- Patients who survive a coma may recover, while ness. A recent case study reported an extraordinary re- others enter the so-called vegetative state, in which covery of verbal communication and motor function in eyes reopen, giving the appearance of wakefulness, but a patient who had remained in a minimally conscious unresponsiveness persists. Soon, regular sleep/waking state for 19 years (Voss et al. 2006). Diffusion tensor cycles follow. Respiration, other autonomic functions MRI showed increased fractional anisotropy (assumed and brainstem functions are relatively preserved, and to reflect myelinated fiber density) in posteromedial stereotypic, reflex-like responses can occur, including cortices, encompassing cuneus and precuneus. These yawning and grunting, but no purposeful behavior. Pa- same areas showed increased glucose metabolism as tients may remain vegetative for a long time or may studied by PET scanning, likely reflecting the neu- emerge to a “minimally conscious state.” This is dis- ronal regrowth paralleling the patient’s clinical recov- tinguished from the vegetative state by the occasional ery. This and other neuroimaging studies of vegetative occurrence of some behaviors that do not appear to be or minimally conscious patients are demonstrating ever purely reflexive, suggesting that some degree of con- more clearly that a purely clinical diagnosis of persis- sciousness may be present. tent loss of consciousness may at times be dramatically Post-mortem analysis in vegetative patients reveals inaccurate. It was already known that patients with that the brainstem and hypothalamus, and specifi- locked-in syndromes due to pontine lesions that left cally the reticular activating system, are largely spared, them almost completely paralyzed may seem unre- which explains why patients look awake. Usually the sponsive, but if they preserve even a minimal ability vegetative state is due to widespread lesions of gray to signal (typically by moving an eye or eyelid up or matter in neocortex and thalamus, to widespread down) they can communicate a rich subjective expe- white-matter damage and diffuse axonal injury, or to rience. What about patients who show no voluntary bilateral thalamic lesions, especially of the paramedian movement at all? Several imaging studies have now thalamic nuclei. It is not clear whether thalamic dam- shown that, even in completely unresponsive patients, age is largely a reflection of diffuse cortical damage as long as significant portions of the thalamocortical (as in metabolic studies of anesthesia, changes in the system are preserved, cognitive stimuli can induce pat- thalamus are much more concentrated and therefore terns of activation similar to those seen in healthy sub- easier to document than changes in cortex) or whether jects (Laureys et al. 2004; Schiff 2006b). As we have even isolated thalamic damage can cause persistent seen in a previous section, stimuli that are not per- unconsciousness. Matrix, calbindin-positive thalamic ceived consciously can still activate appropriate brain cells, which are most numerous within intralaminar areas. Thus, inferring the presence of consciousness nuclei, project diffusely to supragranular layers of cor- may be unwarranted. However, in a recent, thought- tex (Jones 1998) where they facilitate coherent high- provoking study, a clinically vegetative, seemingly un- frequency oscillations (Joliot et al. 1994). Such cells may responsive patient was put in the scanner and asked be especially important in enabling effective interac- to imagine playing tennis or navigating through her tions among many cortical regions: if their activating room. Remarkably, the patient showed fMRI activa- function is lost, patients may remain vegetative even tion patterns of the appropriate cortical regions, exactly though cortical tissue may be relatively intact. Indeed, like healthy subjects. Obviously, these activations could Steven Laureys and colleagues showed that recovery not be due to unconscious processing of stimuli (Owen from a vegetative state was associated with the restora- et al. 2006). Of note, this patient had widespread tion of functional connectivity between intralaminar frontal lesions, while posterior cortex was largely thalamic nuclei and prefrontal and anterior cingulate preserved.
  • 8. 246 Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences Seizures tivity less focally than initially thought (Blumenfeld & The abnormal, hypersynchronous discharge of neu- Taylor 2003; Blumenfeld et al. 2003; Blumenfeld et al. rons is a frequent cause of short-lasting impairments of 2004; Blumenfeld 2005). In fact, it now appears that consciousness. Consciousness is lost or severely affected all seizures causing an impairment of consciousness in so-called generalized seizures, such as absence and are associated with changes in activity in three sets of tonic-clonic seizures, and to a lesser extent in complex brain areas, namely: i) increased activity in the upper partial seizures. Absence seizures, which are more fre- brainstem and medial thalamus; ii) decreased activity quent in children, are momentary lapses of conscious- in the anterior and posterior cingulate, medial frontal ness during which a child stops what she was doing cortex, and precuneus; iii) altered activity in the lateral and stares straight ahead blankly. Absence seizures are and orbital frontal cortex and in the lateral parietal accompanied by spike-and-wave complexes at around cortex. In tonic-clonic seizures, fronto-parietal associ- 3 Hz in the EEG, reflecting cycles of synchronous fir- ation areas show increased activity, while the pattern is ing and silence of large numbers of neurons. There more complex and variable in absence seizures, though is great variability in the degree of unresponsiveness parietal areas are usually deactivated. Complex partial both across subjects and, within the same subject, be- seizures show decreased activity in frontal and parietal tween seizures. Sometimes, simple behaviors such as association cortex, which is associated with the onset repetitive tapping or counting can proceed unimpaired of slow waves similar to those of sleep or anesthesia during the seizures, but more complex tasks come to a (rather than to epileptiform discharges). halt. At this stage, it is not clear which of these three sets Generalized convulsive seizures usually comprise a of areas, alone or in combination, are crucial for the tonic phase of muscle stiffening, followed by a clonic loss of consciousness. However, two things are clear: phase with jerking of the arms and legs. After the con- first, the areas involved in the loss of consciousness vulsion the person may be lethargic or in a state of associated with seizures correspond to those affected confusion for minutes up to hours. During the tonic in sleep, anesthesia, and the vegetative state, pointing phase of a convulsive seizure neural activity is greatly to a common substrate for the most common forms of increased, as indicated by high frequency activity in loss of consciousness; and second, especially during the the EEG. The clonic phase is accompanied by syn- tonic phase of convulsive seizures, it would seem that chronous spikes and waves in the EEG, correspond- consciousness is lost when neurons are excessively and ing to millions of neurons alternately firing in strong synchronously active, rather than inactive. bursts and turning silent. Loss of consciousness during the tonic phase of generalized seizures is noteworthy because it occurs at times when neuronal activity is Changes in the Content of extremely high and synchronous. Consciousness—-Localizing the NCC Partial complex seizures often begin with strange abdominal sensations, fears, premonitions, or auto- As we have seen, much can be learned by studying matic gestures. The person progressively loses contact how brain activity changes with changes in the overall with the environment, exhibits a fixed stare, and is level of consciousness. A complementary approach is unable to respond adequately to questions or com- to examine how brain activity changes when a specific mands. Stereotyped, automatic movements are com- content of consciousness changes—for example, a vi- mon. Complex partial seizures usually last from 15 sec sual stimulus becomes visible or invisible—while every- to 3 min. Seizure activity is usually localized to the thing else, including the overall level of consciousness medial temporal lobe. as well as the sensory input, remains as constant as pos- The diagnosis of seizures is made through clini- sible. Recording spike trains from individual neurons cal observation and EEG recordings. In absence and or measuring hemodynamic signals while the subject tonic-clonic seizures the scalp EEG shows diffuse ab- is looking at a stimulus in an MR scanner allows re- normalities, suggesting a generalized involvement of searchers to investigate what kind of neuronal activity brain networks, whereas in partial complex seizures is correlated with the conscious perception of the stim- the abnormalities are confined to a medial temporal fo- ulus rather than with the mere presentation of the cus on one side. However, neuroimaging studies using stimulus. The goal is to follow the footprints of con- SPECT, PET, and fMRI, and depth EEG recordings sciousness in the brain by ultimately identifying the in humans and animals have revealed that general- neural correlates of consciousness (NCC)—the mini- ized seizures do not affect all brain areas indiscrimi- mal neuronal mechanisms that are jointly sufficient for nately, whereas complex partial seizures alter brain ac- any one specific conscious percept (Crick & Koch 1995,
  • 9. Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness 247 1998, 2003). Thus, every phenomenal, subjective state A Test Case: The NCC in Visual Cortex will have associated NCC: one for seeing a red patch, Many experiments exploit perceptual illusions in another one for seeing grandmother, yet a third one which the physical stimulus remains fixed while the per- for hearing a siren, another one for feeling free to act cept fluctuates. The best known example is the Necker one way or another and so on. Perturbing or inactivat- cube, whose 12 lines can be perceived in one of two ing the NCC for any one specific conscious experience different ways in depth. Another perceptual illusion will affect the percept or cause it to disappear. If the that is easy to vary parametrically is binocular rivalry NCC could be induced artificially, for instance by cor- (Blake & Logothetis 2002): a small image, for example tical microstimulation in a prosthetic device or during a horizontal grating, is presented to the left eye and an- neurosurgery, the subject will experience the associated other image, for example a vertical grating, is shown percept. This definition of the NCC stresses the word to the corresponding location in the right eye. In spite “minimal,” because the question of interest is which of the constant visual stimulus, observers consciously subcomponents of the brain are actually needed. For see the horizontal grating alternate every few seconds instance, while neural activity in the cerebellum may with the vertical one. The brain does not allow for the ultimately affect some behaviors elicited by the presen- simultaneous perception of both images. tation of a stimulus (such as eye movements), it is likely Macaque monkeys can be trained to report whether that such activity has little to do with the generation of they see the left or the right image. The distribution of the conscious percept of that stimulus, and thus is not the switching times and the way in which changing the part of the NCC. contrast in one eye affects the reports leaves little doubt Many questions can be asked: What characterizes that monkeys and humans experience the same basic the NCC for a specific experience? What do the NCC phenomenon. In a series of elegant experiments, Lo- for different experiences have in common? Do the gothetis and colleagues (Leopold & Logothetis 1996; NCC involve just the thalamocortical system, or do Logothetis 1998) recorded from a variety of visual cor- they extend to structures such as the hippocampus, tical areas in the awake macaque monkey while the the claustrum, or the basal ganglia? Do they involve all animal performed a binocular rivalry task. In primary pyramidal neurons in cortex at any given point in time? visual cortex (V1), only a small fraction of cells weakly Or only a subset of cells in frontal lobes that project to modulated their response as a function of the percept of the sensory cortices in the back? Only layer 5 cortical the monkey. The majority of cells responded to one or cells? Neurons that fire in a phasic, synchronous, or the other retinal stimulus with little regard to what the oscillatory manner? Or neurons that are included in animal perceived at the time. In contrast, in a high- reentrant loops? These are some of the proposals that level cortical area such as the inferior temporal (IT) have been advanced over the past years (Chalmers cortex along the ventral pathway, almost all neurons 2000). responded only to the perceptual dominant stimulus, Much of the contemporary work aimed at char- that is, to the stimulus that was being reported. For acterizing the NCC has concentrated on changes in example, when a face and a more abstract design were specific visual contents of consciousness (or awareness, presented, one of these to each eye, a “face” cell fired which is here used interchangeably), in part because only when the animal indicated by its performance visual experience is easy to manipulate experimentally, that it saw the face and not the design presented to and in part because more is known about the anatomy the other eye. This result implies that the NCC involve and function of visual areas in primates than about activity in neurons in inferior temporal cortex (but not, any other brain regions. Visual psychologists have per- of course, that the NCC are local to IT). fected a number of techniques—masking, binocular In a related perceptual phenomenon, flash suppres- rivalry, continuous flash suppression, motion-induced sion (Wolfe 1984), the percept associated with an image blindness, change blindness, inattentional blindness— projected into one eye is suppressed by flashing another in which the seemingly simple and unambiguous rela- image into the other eye (while the original image re- tionship between a physical stimulus in the world, the mains). A methodological advantage over binocular resulting neural activity, and its associated percept is rivalry is that the timing of the perceptual transition disrupted (Kim & Blake 2005). We first consider what is determined by an external trigger rather than by such approaches have revealed about the brain areas an internal event. The majority of responsive cells in that underlie the NCC, focusing specifically on the vi- inferior temporal cortex and in the superior temporal sual system. In the following sections we ask whether sulcus follow the monkey’s behavior—and therefore its the NCC for visual percepts corresponds to some spe- percept. That is, when the animal perceives a cell’s cial kind of neural activity. preferred stimulus, the neuron fires; when the stimulus
  • 10. 248 Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences is present on the retina but is perceptually suppressed, tually invisible line drawings can still be modulated the cell falls silent, even though legions of V1 neu- by selective visual attention. Also, Haynes and Rees rons fire vigorously to the same stimulus (Sheinberg (2005) exploited multivariate decoding techniques to & Logothetis 1997). Single neuron recordings in the read out perceptually suppressed information (the ori- medial temporal lobe of epileptic patients during flash entation of a masked stimulus) from V1 BOLD ac- suppression likewise demonstrate abolition of their re- tivity, even though the stimulus orientation was so effi- sponses when their preferred stimulus is present on the ciently masked that subjects performed at chance levels retina but not seen (Kreiman et al. 2002). when trying to guess the orientation. That is, although In a powerful combination of binocular rivalry and subjects did not give any behavioral indication that flash suppression, a stationary image in one eye can be they saw the orientation of the stimulus, its slant could suppressed for minutes on end by continuously flash- be predicted on a single-trial basis with better-than- ing different images into the other eye (continuous flash chance odds from the V1 (but not from V2 or V3) suppression; Tsuchiya & Koch 2005). This paradigm BOLD signal. lends itself naturally to further investigation of the rela- In conclusion, information pertaining to visual stim- tionship between neural activity—whether assayed at ulus can be registered in primary visual cortex that may the single neuron or at the brain voxel level—and con- or may not be accessible to the subject. It may be mod- scious perception. Imaging experiments with such per- ulated by attention, but it does not appear to correlate ceptual illusions demonstrate quite conclusively that directly with the subject’s percept. In that sense much BOLD activity in the upper stages of the ventral path- of the neural activity in V1 probably does not belong way (e.g., the fusiform face area and the parahippocam- to the NCC. Moreover, as suggested by PET exper- pal place area) follow the percept and not simply the iments in patients in a persistent vegetative state, in retinal stimulus (Tong et al. 1998; Rees & Frith 2007). whom stimuli evoked strong but localized activity in There is a lively debate about the extent to which primary auditory and primary somatosensory cortices neurons in primary visual cortex simply encode the (Laureys et al. 2000b; Laureys et al. 2002), it may well visual stimulus or are directly contributing to the sub- be that none of the primary sensory cortices contributes ject’s conscious percept (Tong 2003). That is, is V1 directly to sensory consciousness. part of the NCC (Crick & Koch 1995)? It is clear that retinal neurons are not part of the NCC for visual ex- periences. While retinal neurons often correlate with Consciousness and Neural Dynamics visual experience, the spiking activity of retinal gan- glion cells does not accord with visual experience (e.g., The studies discussed above indicate that, even there are no photoreceptors at the blind spot; yet no within the cerebral cortex, changes in neural activity do hole in the field of view is apparent, in dreams vivid im- not necessarily correlate with changes in conscious ex- agery occurs despite closed eyes, and so on). A number perience. Also, we saw earlier that most of the cortex is of compelling observations link perception with fMRI active during early NREM sleep and anesthesia, not to BOLD activity in human V1 and even in the lateral mention during generalized seizures, but subjects have geniculate nucleus (LGN) (Tong et al. 1998; Lee et little conscious content to report. Thus, it is natural to al. 2005). These data are at odds with single-neuron suggest that some additional dynamic feature of neural recordings from the monkey. This discrepancy is prob- activity must be present to generate conscious content. ably explained by the often tight relationship between Here we consider the roles of i) sustained versus phasic consciousness and attention that was mentioned above activity, ii) reentrant versus feedforward activity, and (see section “Consciousness and Attention”). Unless at- iii) synchronous or oscillatory activity. tentional effects are carefully controlled for, their neu- ral correlates cannot be untangled from those of con- Sustained versus Phasic Activity sciousness (Huk et al. 2001; Tse et al. 2005). This has A plausible idea is that neural activity may con- now been achieved in an elegant study of Lee, Blake, tribute to consciousness only if it is sustained for a and Heeger (2007). Using a dual-task paradigm they minimum period of time, perhaps around a few hun- found that hemodynamic BOLD activity in human V1 dred ms. At the phenomenological level, there is no reflects attentional processes but does not directly cor- doubt that the “now” of experience unfolds at a time relate with the conscious percept of the subject. The scale comprised between tens and several hundred ms experiment by Bahrami and colleagues (Bahrami et (Bachmann 2000) and in some aspects may even stretch al. 2007) comes to a similar conclusion—they show to one or two seconds (Poppel & Artin 1988). Other that the fMRI signal in V1 associated with percep- experiments have made use of the attentional blink
  • 11. Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness 249 phenomenon: when an observer detects a target in a the target, though they may deny having seen it con- rapid stream of visual stimuli, there is a brief period of sciously. Thus, consciousness would seem to require time during which the detection of subsequent targets that neural activity in appropriate brain structures lasts is impaired. Remarkably, targets that directly follow the for a minimum amount of time, perhaps as much as first target are less impaired than those that follow after is needed to guarantee interactions among multiple 200 to 400 ms (Raymond et al. 1992). By manipulat- areas. ing attention, identical visual stimuli can be made con- On the other hand, other data would seem to sug- scious or unconscious. In such studies, event-related gest that it may actually be the phasic, onset, or off- potentials reflecting early sensory processing (the P1 set discharge of neurons that correlates with experi- and N1 components) were identical for seen and un- ence. The most stringent data come again from studies seen stimuli but quickly diverged around 270 ms, sug- of visual masking (for a review see Macknik 2006). gesting that stimuli only become visible when a sus- To be effective, masking stimuli must either precede tained wave of activation spreads through a distributed (forward masking) or follow (backward masking) tar- network of cortical association areas (Vogel et al. 1998; get stimuli at appropriate time intervals and usually Sergent et al. 2005). need to be spatially contiguous. Macknik, Martinez- More generally, the requirement for sustained dis- Conde, and collaborators showed, using a combina- charge might account for why fast, reflex responses tion of psychophysics, unit recordings in animals, and of the kind mediated by, say, the spinal cord, do not neuroimaging in humans, that for simple, unattended seem to contribute to consciousness. Fast, reflex-like target stimuli, masking stimuli suppress visibility if their responses also take place in the cerebral cortex. For ex- “spatiotemporal edges” overlap with the spatiotempo- ample, the action-oriented dorsal visual stream rapidly ral edges of the targets, that is, if they begin or end adjusts movements that remain outside of conscious- when target stimuli begin or end, in space and time. ness (Goodale & Milner 2005). Perhaps these reflex- They confirmed that such spatiotemporal edges cor- like adjustments to fast-changing aspects of the envi- respond to transient bursts of spikes in primary visual ronment that must be tracked online are incompatible cortex. If these bursts are inhibited, for example if the with the development of sustained discharge patterns. offset discharge elicited by the target stimulus is oblit- By contrast, such sustained patterns may be necessary erated by the onset of the mask, the target becomes for the ventral stream to build a stable representation invisible. Most likely, these spatiotemporal edges of in- of a visual scene. By the same token, if the ventral creased firing are both generated (target stimuli) and stream could be forced to behave in a reflex-like man- suppressed (masking stimuli) by mechanisms of lateral ner, it should cease to be part of the NCC. Indeed, inhibition, which are ubiquitous in sensory systems this can be achieved by pushing the ventral system to (Macknik 2006). perform ultra-rapid categorizations such as deciding Additional evidence for the importance of phasic, whether a natural image contains an animal or not transient activation of neurons in determining the visi- (Thorpe et al. 1996; Bacon-Mace et al. 2005; Kirch- bility of stimuli comes from studies of microsaccades— ner & Thorpe 2006). In such cases, a sweep of activity the small, involuntary movements that our eyes make travels from the retina through several stages of feedfor- continually (Martinez-Conde et al. 2004). If microsac- ward connections along the hierarchy of ventral visual cades are counteracted by image stabilization on the areas, until it elicits an appropriate categorization re- retina, stationary objects fade and become completely sponse. This process takes as little as 150 ms, which invisible. In a recent study (Martinez-Conde et al. leaves only about 10 ms of processing per stage. Thus, 2006), subjects were asked to fixate a central dot (which only a few spikes can be fired before the next stage tends to reduce microsaccades) while attending to a produces its output, yet they are sufficient to spec- surrounding circle. Soon, the circle fades and merges ify selective responses for orientation, motion, depth, into the background (the Troxler illusion). It was found color, shape, and even animals, faces, or places con- that before a fading period, the probability, rate, and veying most of the relevant information about the magnitude of microsaccades decreased. Before transi- stimulus (Hung et al. 2005). While this fast feedfor- tions toward visibility, the probability, rate, and mag- ward sweep within the ventral system is sufficient for nitude of microsaccades increased, compatible with the near-automatic categorization of stimuli and a be- the hypothesis that microsaccades are indeed neces- havioral response, it seems insufficient to generate a sary for visibility. Importantly, in macaque monkeys, conscious percept (VanRullen & Koch 2003). For ex- when an optimally oriented line was centered over ample, if another image (the mask) is flashed soon after the receptive field of cells in V1, the cells’ activity in- the target image, subjects are still able to categorize creased after microsaccades and tended to emit bursts
  • 12. 250 Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences (Martinez-Conde et al. 2002), suggesting again that (Hebb 1949), implementing hypothesis testing through phasic activity may be crucial for visibility. resonances (Grossberg 1999), linking present with past One should remember, however, that the impor- (Edelman & Mountcastle 1978; Edelman 1989), and tance of phasic discharges for stimulus awareness has subject with object (Damasio 1999). only been demonstrated for early visual cortex; but, A more concrete reason why reentrant activity is as we saw above, the NCC are more likely to lie an attractive candidate for the NCC is that it travels elsewhere. Psychophysically, masking is similarly effec- through back connections, of which the cerebral cortex tive when masking stimuli are presented monoptically is extraordinarily rich (Felleman & Van Essen 1991). (through the same eye as the target) and dichoptically In primates, feedforward connections originate mainly (through the other eye). The analysis of fMRI data in supragranular layers and terminate in layer 4. Feed- in humans shows that a correlate of monoptic visual back connections instead originate in both superficial masking can be found in all retinotopic visual areas, and deep layers and usually terminate outside of layer whereas dichoptic masking is only seen in retinotopic 4. The sheer abundance of back connections in sensory areas downstream of V2 within the occipital lobe (Tse regions suggests that they ought to serve some impor- et al. 2005), suggesting an anatomical lower bound for tant purpose, and giving rise to a conscious percept the NCC. Thus, it could be that phasic onset and off- might just fit the bill. However, back connections and set discharges are important not in and of themselves, associated reentrant volleys are just as numerous be- but because they are particularly effective in activating tween V1 and visual thalamus, which is usually denied downstream areas that directly support the NCC. In any direct contribution to awareness. Also, there does these downstream areas, perhaps, the NCC may ac- not seem to be any lack of back connections within tually require sustained firing. Indeed, the duration of the dorsal stream. It should be emphasized that the the activation of face-selective neurons in IT is strongly strength and termination pattern of back connections correlated with the visibility of masked faces (Rolls et seem more suited to a modulatory/synchronizing role al. 1999). than to driving their target neurons. For example, the focal inactivation of area 18 can slightly increase or Reentrant versus Feedforward Activity decrease discharge rates of units in area 17, but it Another possibility is that it is not so much sustained does not change their feature selectivity for location firing that triggers the awareness of a stimulus, but and orientation (Martinez-Conde et al. 1999). Also, rather the occurrence of a “reentrant” wave of activity the numerosity of backward connections is a natural (also described as recurrent, recursive, or reverberant) consequence of the hierarchical organization of feed- from higher to lower cortical areas. In this view, when a forward ones. For instance, cells in the LGN are not stimulus evokes a feedforward sweep of activity, it is not oriented, while cells in area 17 are. To be unbiased, seen consciously, but it becomes so when the feedfor- feedback to any one LGN cell should come from area ward sweep is joined by a reentrant sweep (Lamme & 17 cells of all orientations, which requires many con- Roelfsema 2000). This logic could apply both to early nections; on the other hand, since at any given time sensory areas such as V1 and to higher areas such as IT. only area 17 cells corresponding to a given orientation For example, when face neurons in the fusiform face would be active, feedback effects would not be strong. area are first activated, we would not see a face con- If they were, properties of area 17 cells, such as orienta- sciously, although we could turn our eyes toward it or tion selectivity, would be transferred upon LGN cells, press a button to indicate our unconscious categoriza- which they are not (to a first approximation). Back- tion as a face. However, when face-selective neurons ward signals certainly play a role in sensory function: receive a backward volley from some higher area, for for instance, they can mediate some extraclassical re- example frontal cortex, the face would become visible. ceptive field effects, provide a natural substrate for both This view is based on several considerations. An im- attentional modulation and imagery, and can perhaps portant one, though rarely confessed, is that a mere dynamically route feedforward processing according sequence of feedforward processing steps seems far to prior expectations. But are backward signals really too “straightforward” and mechanical to offer a sub- critical for consciousness? strate for subjective experience. Reentrant processes, The most intriguing data in support of a role for by “closing the loop” between past and present activ- reentrant activity in conscious perception have come ity, or between predicted and actual versions of the from neurophysiological experiments. In awake mon- input, would seem to provide a more fertile substrate keys trained to signal whether or not they see a salient for giving rise to reverberations (Lorente de N´ 1938), o figure on a background, the early, feedforward response generating emergent properties through cell assemblies of V1 neurons was the same, no matter whether or not
  • 13. Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness 251 the monkey saw the figure (Super et al. 2001). How- stimuli that are processed in visual cortex. If, around ever, a later response component was suppressed when 100 ms later, a TMS pulse was applied to V1, the stim- the monkey did not see the figure. Light anesthesia also ulus became perceptually invisible, although on forced eliminated this later component without affecting the choice subjects could still discriminate orientation or initial response. Late components are thought to reflect color. This result indicates that, without any overt par- reentrant volleys from higher areas, although other ticipation of V1, stimuli can reach extrastriate areas studies have disputed this claim (Rossi et al. 2001). without eliciting a conscious percept, just as in blind- The late response component crucial for the visibil- sight patients. It also suggests that, since the forward ity of stimuli under backward masking might also be sweep reaches V1 after just 30 or 40 ms, the TMS pulse due to a reentrant volley (Lamme & Roelfsema 2000). may abolish the awareness of the stimulus not so much In this case the timing of maximal backward mask- by blocking feedforward transmission as by interfer- ing should be independent of target duration, since it ing with the backward volley (see also Ro et al. 2003). would be determined exclusively by the time needed On the other hand, it cannot be ruled out that the for the early component to travel to higher areas and TMS pulse may act instead by triggering a cortical– return to primary visual cortex. Instead, the timing of thalamo–cortical volley that interferes with the offset maximal masking depends on the timing of target off- discharge triggered by the stimulus, as may indeed be set, suggesting that the component that is obliterated the case in backward masking. is a feedforward offset discharge, not a reentrant one Yet another study, this time using fMRI, examined (Macknik 2006). Moreover, the late component can be the neural correlates of brightness (perceptual light- dissociated from a behavioral response simply by rais- ness) using backward masking. The psychometric vis- ing the decision criterion (Super et al. 2001), and it ibility function was not correlated with the stimulated can occur in the absence of report during change and portion of V1, but with downstream visual regions, in- inattentional blindness (Scholte et al. 2006). Perhaps in cluding fusiform cortex, parietal–functional areas, and such cases subjective experience is present but, due to with the sectors of V1 responding to the unstimulated an insufficient involvement of frontal areas, it cannot be surround (Haynes et al. 2005). Remarkably, visibility reported (Block 2005; Tsuchiya & Koch 2005; Lamme was also correlated with the amount of coupling (ef- 2006). But then, by the same token, why should we fective connectivity) between fusiform cortex and the rule out subjective experience during the feedforward portion of V1 that responded to the surround. Once sweep? again, this result could be explained by the activation Another main source of evidence for a role of reen- of reentrant connections, though fMRI cannot distin- trant volleys in consciousness comes from experiments guish between forward and backward influences. using TMS. In an early experiment, Pascual-Leone and Walsh applied TMS to V5 to elicit large, mov- Synchronization and Oscillations ing phosphenes (Pascual-Leone & Walsh 2001). They Another influential idea is that consciousness may then applied another, subthreshold TMS pulse to a require the synchronization, at a fine temporal scale, corresponding location in V1. When TMS to V1 was of large populations of neurons distributed over many delivered after TMS to V5 (+5 to +45 ms), subjects cortical areas, in particular via rhythmic discharges often did not see the V5 phosphene, and when they in the gamma range (30–70 Hz and beyond) (Crick saw one, it was not moving. Their interpretation was & Koch 1990). The emphasis on synchrony ties in that disruption of activity in V1 at the time of arrival well with the common assumption that consciousness of a reentrant volley from V5 interferes with the ex- requires the “binding” together of a multitude of at- perience of attributes encoded by V5. In a subsequent tributes within a single experience, as when we see study (Silvanto et al. 2005), it was shown that, when a a rich visual scene containing multiple objects and subthreshold pulse was applied over V5, followed 10 attributes that is nevertheless perceived as a unified − 40 ms later by a suprathreshold pulse over V1, sub- whole (Singer 1999). According to this view, the NCC jects reported a V5-like phosphene (large and moving), of such an experience would include two aspects: first, rather than a V1 phosphene (small and stationary). the underlying activation pattern (groups of neurons Their interpretation was that activity in V5 that, on that have increased their firing rates) would be widely its own, is insufficient to induce a moving percept can distributed across different areas of the cerebral cor- produce such a percept if the level of induced activity tex, each specialized in signaling a different object in V1 is high enough. or attribute within the scene; and second, the firing In another study (Boyer et al. 2005), subjects where of these activated neurons would be synchronized on shown either an oriented bar or a colored patch— a fast time scale to signal their binding into a single
  • 14. 252 Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences percept. In this respect, synchrony seems ideally suited consciously perceived words induced theta oscillations to signal relatedness: for example, in the presence of a in multiple cortical regions until the test stimulus was red square, some neurons would respond to the pres- presented and a decision reached, while a burst of ence of a square, while others would respond to the gamma activity occurred over central and frontal leads presence of the color red. If they synchronize at a fast just prior to and during the presentation of the test time scale, they would indicate to other groups of neu- stimulus. Importantly, the earliest event distinguishing rons that there is a red square, “binding” the two fea- conscious and unconscious processing was not visi- tures together (Tononi et al. 1992). By contrast, signal- ble in the power changes of oscillations but in their ing relatedness by increased firing rates alone would be phase locking. About 180 ms after presentation of stim- more cumbersome and probably slower (Singer 1999). uli that were consciously perceived, induced gamma Also, fine-temporal-scale synchrony has the welcome oscillations recorded from a large number of regions property of disambiguating among multiple objects— exhibited precise phase locking both within and across if a green cross were present simultaneously with the hemispheres for around 100 ms. These results have red square, cross and green neurons would also be ac- been interpreted to indicate that a transient event of tive, but false conjunctions would be avoided by precise gamma synchrony resets multiple parallel processes to phase locking (Tononi et al. 1992). Moreover, compu- a common time frame. The global theta rhythm that tational models predict that, for the same level of firing, follows after this trigger event could provide the time synchronous input is more effective on target neurons frame for allowing a global integration of information than asynchronous input (Abeles 1991; Tononi et al. provided by sensory inputs and internal sources. Or 1992), and indeed synchrony makes a difference to the perhaps beta–gamma synchrony could enable the in- outputs to the rest of the brain (Brecht et al. 1999; tegration of activity patterns within local cortical areas, Schoffelen et al. 2005). Finally, large-scale models pre- while theta synchrony would permit the integration of dict that synchrony in the gamma range occurs due to more globally distributed patterns: the more global the the reciprocal connectivity and loops within the thala- representation, the longer the time scale for the inte- mocortical system (Lumer et al. 1997a, b), and indeed gration of distributed information. phase alignment between distant groups of neurons in It would be premature to conclude, however, that the gamma range anticipates by a few ms an increase synchrony in one or another frequency band is neces- in gamma-band power (Womelsdorf et al. 2007). In sarily a marker of NCC. As revealed by an increasing this respect, oscillatory activity, even when subthresh- number of EEG, MEG, electrocorticography, and mul- old, could further facilitate synchronous interactions tiunit recordings, cognitive tasks are associated with by biasing neurons to discharge within the same time complex modes of synchronous coupling among pop- frame (Engel et al. 2001). ulations of neurons that shift rapidly both within and Experimental evidence concerning the role of syn- across different frequency bands, within and between chrony/synchronous oscillations in perceptual oper- areas, and in relation to the timing of the task (Wom- ations was initially obtained in primary visual areas elsdorf et al. 2007). It would rather seem that, given of anesthetized animals (for a review see Singer & the brain’s remarkable connectivity, synchrony is an in- Gray 1995). For example, in primary visual cortex, evitable accompaniment of neural activity, and that it neurons have been found that respond to a coher- is bound to change just as activity patterns change, ent object by synchronizing their firing in the gamma depending on the precise experimental conditions. range. Stimulus-specific, gamma-range synchroniza- Whether a particular kind of synchrony, for example tion is greatly facilitated when the EEG is activated in the gamma range, is uniquely associated with con- by stimulating the mesencephalic reticular formation sciousness is still unclear. For example, high beta and (Munk et al. 1996; Herculano-Houzel et al. 1999). It is gamma synchrony can be found in virtually every brain similarly facilitated by attention (Roelfsema et al. 1997) region investigated, including some that are unlikely to and by increases in a dominant stimulus under binoc- contribute directly to consciousness. Also, it is not yet ular rivalry even though firing rates may not change clear whether synchrony in the gamma range vanishes (Fries et al. 1997, 2001). during early NREM sleep, during anesthesia, or even Other evidence has come from EEG studies of phase during seizures. Human studies are still inconsistent locking in humans. A recent study compared the neu- on this point, whereas animal studies show a paradox- ral correlates of words that were consciously perceived ical increase in gamma synchrony when rats lose the with those of masked words that had been processed righting reflex (thought to correspond more or less to and semantically decoded but had remained uncon- the loss of consciousness in humans; see Imas et al. scious (Melloni et al. 2007). The results showed that 2005a, b). It would seem that there can be synchrony
  • 15. Tononi and Koch: The Neural Correlates of Consciousness 253 without consciousness, though perhaps not conscious- are organized in a radically different way from human ness without synchrony, at least in mammalian brains. brains? Finally, there are some difficult conceptual prob- lems in characterizing synchrony as an essential ingre- Consciousness as Integrated Information dient that unifies perceptual states and thereby makes To address these questions, it would seem that we them conscious. While many experiences do indeed need a theoretical approach that tries to establish, at the involve several different elements and attributes that fundamental level, what consciousness is, how it can be are “bound” together into a unified percept, there are measured, and what requisites a physical system must many other experiences, equally conscious, that do not satisfy in order to generate it. The integrated information seem to require much binding at all: for instance, an theory of consciousness represents such an approach experience of pure darkness or of pure blue, or a loud (Tononi 2004b). sound that briefly occupies consciousness and has no According to the theory, the most important prop- obvious internal structure, would merely seem to re- erty of consciousness is that is extraordinarily informa- quire the strong activation of the relevant neurons, with tive. This is because, whenever you experience a par- no need for signaling relatedness to other elements, ticular conscious state, it rules out a huge number of and thus no need for synchrony. Also, the idea that alternative experiences. Classically, the reduction of the NCC of a given conscious experience are given by uncertainty among a number of alternatives consti- active neurons bound by synchrony discounts the im- tutes information. For example, you lie in bed with portance of inactive ones: information specifying that eyes open and experience pure darkness and silence. particular unified experience must be conveyed both This is one of the simplest experiences you might have, by which neurons are active and which are not, yet for one that may not be thought as conveying much in- inactive neurons there does not seem to be anything formation. One should realize, however, that the in- to bind. On the other hand, if most neurons in the formativeness of what you just experienced lies not in cortex were to become active hypersynchronously, as how complicated it is to describe, but in how many is the case in generalized seizures, they should result in alternatives were ruled out when you experienced it: maximal “binding,” but consciousness vanishes rather you could have experienced any one frame from any of than become more vivid.. innumerable movies, or the smoke and flames of your room burning, or any other possible scene, but you did not—instead, you experienced darkness and silence. Consciousness from a Theoretical This means that when you experienced darkness and Perspective silence, whether you think or not of what was ruled out (and you typically don’t), you actually gained access to Progress in the study of the NCC will hopefully a large amount of information. This point is so simple lead to a better understanding of what distinguishes that its importance has been overlooked. neural structures or processes that are associated with It is essential to realize, however, that the informa- consciousness from those that are not. But even if we tion associated with the occurrence of a conscious state come closer to this goal, we still need to understand is integrated information. When you experience a par- why certain structures and processes have a privileged ticular conscious state, that conscious state is an inte- relationship with subjective experience. For example, grated whole—it cannot be subdivided into compo- why is it that neurons in thalamocortical circuits are nents that are experienced independently. For exam- essential for conscious experience, whereas cerebellar ple, the conscious experience of the particular phrase neurons, despite their huge numbers, are not? And you are reading now cannot be experienced as subdi- what is wrong with many cortical circuits, including vided into, say, the conscious experience of how the those in V1, that makes them unsuitable to yield subjec- words look independently of the conscious experience tive experience? Or why is it that consciousness wanes of how they sound in your mind. Similarly, you cannot during slow-wave sleep early in the night, despite lev- experience visual shapes independently of their color, els of neural firing in the thalamocortical system that or perceive the left half of the visual field of view inde- are comparable to those in quiet wakefulness? Other pendently of the right half. questions are even more difficult to address in the ab- Based on these and other considerations, the theory sence of a theory. For example, is consciousness present claims that the level of consciousness of a physical system is in animals that have a nervous system considerably related to the repertoire of causal states (information) available to different from ours? And what about computerized the system as a whole (integration). That is, whenever a sys- robots or other artifacts that behave intelligently but tem enters a particular state though causal interactions
  • 16. 254 Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences among its elements, it is conscious in proportion to how that bear some structural resemblance to different parts many system states it has thereby ruled out, provided of the brain (Tononi 2004b, 2005). For example, by us- these are states of the system as a whole, not decom- ing computer simulations, it is possible to show that posable into states of causally independent parts. More high requires networks that conjoin functional spe- precisely, the theory introduces a measure of integrated cialization (due to its specialized connectivity, each ele- information called , quantifying the reduction of un- ment has a unique functional role within the network) certainty (i.e., the information) that is generated when a with functional integration (there are many pathways system enters a particular state through causal interac- for interactions among the elements.). In very rough tions among its parts, above and beyond the informa- terms, this kind of architecture is characteristic of the tion that is generated independently within the parts mammalian thalamo-cortical system: different parts of themselves (hence integrated information). The parts the cerebral cortex are specialized for different func- should be chosen in such a way that they can account tions, yet a vast network of connections allows these for as much nonintegrated (independent) information parts to interact profusely. Indeed, the thalamo-cortical as possible. system is precisely the part of the brain which cannot If a system has a positive value of (and it is not be severely impaired without loss of consciousness. included within a larger subset having higher ) it is Conversely, is low for systems that are made up of called a complex. For a complex, and only for a complex, small, quasi-independent modules. This may be why it is appropriate to say that when it enters a particular the cerebellum, despite its large number of neurons, state, it generates an amount of integrated information does not contribute much to consciousness: its synaptic corresponding to . Since integrated information can organization is such that individual patches of cerebel- only be generated within a complex and not outside lar cortex tend to be activated independently of one its boundaries, consciousness is necessarily subjective, another, with little interaction between distant patches private, and related to a single point of view or per- (Cohen & Yarom 1998; Bower 2002). spective (Tononi & Edelman 1998). Some properties Computer simulations also show that units along of complexes are worth pointing out. A given physical multiple, segregated incoming or outgoing pathways system, such as a brain, is likely to contain more than are not incorporated within the repertoire of the main one complex, many small ones with low values, and complex. This may be why neural activity in afferent perhaps a few large ones. We suspect that in the brain pathways (perhaps as far as V1), though crucial for there is at any given time a complex of comparatively triggering this or that conscious experience, does not much higher , which we call the main complex. Also, contribute directly to conscious experience; nor does a complex can be causally connected to elements that activity in efferent pathways (perhaps starting with pri- are not part of it through ports-in and ports-out. In that mary motor cortex), though it is crucial for reporting case, elements that are part of the complex contribute each different experience. to its conscious experience, while elements that are not The addition of many parallel cycles also generally part of it do not, even though they may be connected does not change the composition of the main complex, to it and exchange information with it through ports-in although values can be altered. Instead, cortical and ports-out. One should also note that the value and subcortical cycles or loops implement specialized of a complex is dependent on both spatial and tem- subroutines that are capable of influencing the states poral scales that determine what counts as a state of of the main thalamocortical complex without joining the underlying system. In general, the relevant spatial it. Such informationally insulated cortico-subcortical and temporal scales are those that jointly maximize loops could constitute the neural substrates for many (Tononi 2004b). In the case of the brain, the spa- unconscious processes that can affect and be affected tial elements and time scales that maximize may by conscious experience (Baars 1988; Tononi 2004a, be local collections of neurons such as minicolumns b), such as those that enable object recognition, lan- and periods of time comprised between tens and hun- guage parsing, or translating our vague intentions into dreds of milliseconds, respectively, though at this stage the right words. At this stage, however, it is hard to say it is difficult to adjudicate between minicolumns and precisely which cortical circuits may be informationally individual neurons. insulated. Are primary sensory cortices organized like massive afferent pathways to a main complex “higher Accounting for Neurobiological up” in the cortical hierarchy? Is much of prefrontal Observations cortex organized like a massive efferent pathway? Do Measuring and finding complexes is not easy for certain cortical areas, such as those belonging to the realistic systems, but it can be done for simple networks dorsal visual stream, remain partly segregated from