SlideShare une entreprise Scribd logo
1  sur  7
Civil Society and the Problem of 
Global Democracy 
MICHAEL GOODHART 
Civil society is among the most widely discussed and 
frequently deployed concepts in 
contemporary political science. To normative political 
theorists it is a critical concept 
representing an ideal of inclusive participation and 
deliberation. Many empirically 
minded students of democracy emphasize its role in 
fostering democratic transitions 
and facilitating democratic consolidation. Moreover, political 
scientists of many 
stripes have taken an interest in the various actors who 
populate civil society – 
from non-governmental organizations (NGOs) and new 
social movements to the 
more traditional interest groups emphasized in the pluralist 
framework. Of late 
there has been a veritable explosion of new work on civil 
society in its many 
guises, and while some skeptical voices have questioned the 
sanguine views currently 
in vogue, the judgment expressed in the Times Literary 
Supplement remains apt: ‘the 
very phrase [civil society] is becoming motherhood-and-apple- 
pie’.1 
Ironically, as enthusiasm about civil society’s role in 
supporting democracy 
grows, the prospects of democracy itself seem to be 
worsening. Over the past 
decade, the accelerating pace of globalization has fueled 
alarm over the vitality of 
state-level democracy and over the lack of democracy in 
international, transnational 
and global institutions and interactions. Democratic deficits 
and disjunctures, created 
by the seemingly relentless advance of globalization and by 
the state’s alleged 
‘retreat’ or ‘erosion’ before it, have forced scholars to 
reconsider democracy’s 
foundations at the nation-state level and to contemplate 
schemes for implementing it 
globally. ‘The problem of global democracy’ is a shorthand 
for such concerns about 
globalization’s perceived adverse effects; quite basically, the 
problem is whether and 
how democracy can weather these challenges. 
Perhaps inevitably, given the concurrence of these two 
significant developments, 
many scholars and activists have begun to conceive of an 
emergent ‘global civil 
society’ as a model or strategy for global democracy and 
democratization. These theorists 
and practitioners increasingly adopt global civil society 
(GCS) as a conceptual 
framework for supranational democracy and as a concrete 
political project. They 
propose that, like its domestic counterpart, GCS has great 
potential as a site and mechanism 
of global democracy and as a vehicle for democratizing 
supranational governance. 
This article critically evaluates these claims, advancing two 
closely related 
arguments. The first, substantive argument is that 
proponents of global democracy 
through GCS do not adequately conceptualize global 
democracy or democratization: 
civil society’s purported democratic functions and effects do 
not and cannot work in 
the supranational setting. The second, epistemological 
argument is that the failure of 
GCS as an account of global democracy and democratization 
reflects broader challenges 
in theorizing global politics and global democracy. 
Democratic enthusiasm 
for GCS confuses the challenges facing democracy and 
mistakenly relies on concepts 
and theories of democracy rooted in Westphalian politics in 
addressing them. As the 
problems with GCS accounts illustrate, meeting these 
challenges requires a global 
democratic theory, not simply the global application or 
extension of existing democratic 
theory. 
The article has four sections. The first introduces the 
problem of global democracy 
and briefly reviews the main claims for conceiving GCS as a 
model or strategy for 
global democracy in response to this problem. These claims 
draw on two models 
of civil society’s democratic functions and effects in the state, 
the neo-Tocquevillian 
and anti-authoritarian models. Sections two and three analyse 
each model in turn, 
showing that neither successfully survives transposition to the 
supranational sphere. 
Civil society cannot perform its democratic role because that 
role depends on conceptual 
and institutional relationships that do not hold globally. The 
final section shows 
that the shortcomings of GCS as a model for global democracy 
reflect common epistemological 
errors in the analysis of supranational politics and the 
theorization of 
global democracy. These errors include conceiving global 
politics in statist ways 
and treating the problem of global democracy mainly as a 
problem of size or 
reach. A theory of global democracy must reconsider the 
meaning and institutional 
form of democracy in light of the distinctive characteristics of 
globalization and 
supranational governance. 
Before beginning, however, two potential points of confusion 
should be 
pre-empted. First, the argument here does not question the 
political significance of 
supranational network and associational activity. A vast 
empirical literature documents 
how GCS can influence policy and constrain global governance. 
Moreover, 
many GCS actors are motivated by and promote norms of 
democracy and human 
rights. These facts are acknowledged and appreciated, and 
nothing here should be 
taken to prejudge what role supranational network and 
associational actors might 
2 DEMOCRATIZATION 
play in achieving and sustaining global democracy. Second, and 
following closely 
from the preceding point, the argument here is not about 
whether GCS is a good 
thing or has positive effects on global governance. Undoubtedly 
it can do so, and 
numerous scholars have paid careful attention to how.2 The 
argument rather concerns 
whether GCS provides an adequate and appropriate model for 
global democracy 
and strategy for global democratization – that is, whether we 
should conceive 
global democracy in terms of GCS. The negative conclusion is 
based on a conceptual 
critique of global democracy on the GCS model, not on a denial 
or rejection of the 
positive potential contributions of supranational network and 
associational activity. 
GCS: A Model for Global Democracy? 
Before considering arguments proposing GCS as a model for 
global democracy, a few 
words about the problem of global democracy are in order. 
Globalization is widely 
perceived as a threat to democracy within states and as 
intensifying the need for 
greater democracy among states. While a full discussion of 
these issues is beyond 
the scope of this article the crucial points can be sketched 
briefly.3 Globalization is 
a contested concept, one encompassing change in 
technological, military, cultural, 
political, and perhaps especially economic domains. The 
essence of this change 
can be characterized as supranationalization, a shift in the locus 
or density of 
social activity and interactions (including governance) from the 
local and national 
to the supranational (international, transnational and global) 
level. This quite 
general understanding of globalization makes its challenges for 
democracy seemingly 
clear. First, globalization creates democratic disjunctures, which 
describe the gap 
between existing state-level democratic procedures and 
institutions and the increasingly 
supranational character of many political issues, including terrorism, public 
health, the environment and, most controversially, trade, investment and 
economic 
integration. Second, globalization exposes and exacerbates democratic 
deficits, 
which describe the lack of transparency, accountability and representation 
in existing 
supranational institutions.4 The problem of global democracy is how 
meaningfully to 
realize democracy outside its traditional theoretical and institutional 
boundaries in the 
Westphalian state without further attenuating democracy within them. 
Many scholars attribute the rapid development of GCS to a shift of power 
away 
from states to both supranational and subnational authorities. This shift, 
they 
contend, creates a need for new actors to assume many of the functions 
previously 
performed by states, including identity formation and preservation, 
regulation of 
the economy, protection of the environment and articulation of the needs 
and interests 
of citizens. The actors populating GCS fill a void created by the retreat of 
the state and 
the spread of global capitalism,5 in effect bridging democratic disjunctures 
and 
compensating for democratic deficits. Growing numbers of democratic 
theorists 
and activists, observing the proliferation of supranational NGOs and 
transnational 
social movements (TSMs) and impressed by their increasing role and 
influence in 
supranational affairs, talk about GCS as a model or framework for global 
democracy.6 
To its proponents, the role of GCS as a democratic model originates in and 
is 
‘legitimated by the growing competence of societal actors relative to the 
inability 
CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 3 
of states to confront problems that increasingly escape the grasp of 
territorially 
delimited actors’.7 On this view, the nascent sphere of GCS overlays the 
existing 
political spaces of states and international politics, allowing ‘for the 
construction of 
new political spaces . . . delineated by networks of economic, social and 
cultural 
relations . . . occupied by the conscious association of actors, in physically 
separated 
locations, who link themselves together in networks for particular political 
and social 
purposes’.8 A ‘medley of boundary-eclipsing actors – social movements, 
interest 
groups, indigenous peoples, cultural groups, and global citizens – are [sic] 
seen to 
be constructing networks, knowledges and practices that entail a 
reshaping of the 
political architecture of international relations’.9 These networks and 
associations 
counterbalance the ‘state-like’ system of global governance made up of 
institutionalized 
regulatory arrangements (regimes) and less formalized norms, rules and 
procedures.10 
Proponents see numerous democratic functions and effects in the activities 
of 
these new transnational actors. The constituent groups of GCS are 
voluntary and 
often issue or identity related; they seek social or political influence and 
generate 
bonds and social capital across state borders. These groups serve as 
channels for information, 
creating opportunities for transnational learning and dialogue that 
facilitate 
the recognition of common experiences of global problems and the 
emergence of 
transnational identities.11 According to Smith, global groups and networks 
also represent 
‘the most promising source of enhanced democratic participation in the 
emerging 
global polity’.12 In her view, participation in TSM organizations ‘helps 
enfranchise individuals and groups that are formally excluded from 
participation 
in international institutions. It strengthens the global public sphere by 
mobilizing 
this disenfranchised public into discussions of global issues, thereby 
democratizing 
the global political process’. Participation thus serves a representative 
function that 
widens discussion of the global public good and expands both the 
agenda and the 
range of policy options considered. 
Transnational networks, ranging in intensity from informal contacts 
based around 
shared values to full-fledged TSMs, characterize activism targeting 
particular global 
issues and institutions.13 Their influence derives from their efficacy in 
shaping the 
international agenda, in negotiating within various international 
forums, in strengthening 
and supporting local organizations and networks, and in using their 
moral 
authority to pressure officials and raise consciousness.14 Such 
networks frequently 
draw on already-established norms of democracy and human rights to 
construct 
frames for collective action and opposition to oppressive regimes.15 
GCS can claim 
some success in influencing states and international regimes; the 
expanding role of 
NGOs and TSM organizations in global summits and conferences and 
even in 
some formal governance regimes further encourages the hope that 
they might play 
an important role in democratization.16 Dryzek, for example, 
concludes that GCS 
can provide democratic legitimacy to the emerging system of global 
governance. 
Deepening transnational discourses facilitated by NGOs and TSMs have 
become 
dense enough in his view to constitute discursive networks capable of 
shaping 
global opinion.17 Networks promoting transnational deliberation (and 
thus shaping 
transnational discourse) are ‘the most appropriate available 
institutional expression 
4 DEMOCRATIZATION 
of a dispersed capacity to engage in deliberation’ that promotes 
democratic legitimacy. 
18 Seen in this broader context, one aim of GCS is to reconnect 
politics with 
the moral purpose and values associated with democracy. Falk and 
others refer to 
this process as one of ‘globalization from below’, in which grass- and 
cyber-roots 
activities (will) remake the international order through civilizing 
activities based in 
a commitment to progressive political norms.19 
Two related but distinct kinds of claim about the democratic nature of 
GCS are 
discernible in the arguments just surveyed. One is that institutional 
activity within 
GCS – including the transfer of information, creation of social bonds, 
representation 
of diverse interests and deliberation on important issues – is 
democratic and thus 
helps make global governance (more) democratic. The other is that 
networks and 
movements committed to democratic and human rights norms will 
transform the 
international regime through opposition to and renewal of existing 
non-democratic 
governance structures. These two types of claim evoke two different 
models or 
ideal types of civil society in the state, what are called here the neo- 
Tocquevillian 
and anti-authoritarian models.20 Because GCS is complex and 
embryonic, these 
models have become blurred and confused in claims about the 
democratic nature 
of GCS. In order to gain analytic leverage in evaluating them, the 
following 
account specifies the purported democratic functions and effects of 
each model at 
the domestic level and then considers whether they obtain in the 
global context. 
The analysis focuses on the often-implicit assumptions underlying 
these democratic 
claims and on their empirical, pragmatic and normative implications.21 
The Neo-Tocquevillian Model 
The neo-Tocquevillian model emphasizes the democratic functions and 
effects of 
associational life within a liberal or liberal-democratic state. It 
theorizes this associational 
sphere as autonomous, occupying a conceptual space between the 
individual
and the state. Civil society ‘[names] the space of uncoerced 
human association and 
also the set of relational networks . . . that fill this space’,22 
although there is disagreement 
about whether to include the family and market actors and 
institutions in this 
definition.23 Liberals, communitarians (republicans) and 
critical theorists have all 
embraced some variant of this model.24 
The essence of the neo-Tocquevillian approach is ‘that 
largely apolitical associations 
that crosscut the major lines of conflict within a society will 
help produce 
the moderation and the compromising spirit necessary for 
efficient democratic 
governance’.25 These institutions ‘counterbalance the state 
and, while not preventing 
the state from fulfilling its role of keeper of the peace and 
arbitrator between major 
interests, can nevertheless prevent it from dominating and 
atomizing the rest of 
society’.26 Activity and participation within the autonomous 
sphere recognize and 
promote the values of publicity, participation and state 
accountability by mobilizing 
independent political actors and protecting subjective rights 
in a context governed 
by the rule of law.27 Some theorists correlate the sheer 
density of associations with 
the vitality of democracy, while others focus on the habits 
and values inculcated 
by citizens’ immersion in associational life. Involvement with 
voluntary associations 
CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 5 
teaches individuals to put common values ahead of selfish 
interests, creates social 
capital and helps to undercut the tremendous power of the 
modern bureaucratic 
state.28 Many theorists of discursive or deliberative 
democracy see civil society’s 
independent networks and associations as an approximation 
of an ideal discursive 
arena where open, unconstrained deliberation generates 
norms that produce consensus 
and guide democratic practice.29 
As this discussion makes clear, the neo-Tocquevillian model 
is not merely a 
descriptive account of civil society and its operations; nor is 
it a complete account 
of democracy. Rather, it tries to explain how a well-functioning 
civil society supports 
and facilitates democracy. Five distinct claims can be 
distilled from the foregoing 
account. First, participation in voluntary associations 
educates people to be good 
democratic citizens; they learn to co-operate, to put public 
ends ahead of private 
ones, and so forth. Second, participation creates a 
moderate public and moderates 
public opinion. Third, participation helps to build social 
capital among individuals, 
giving cohesion to communities and amplifying citizens’ 
capabilities. Fourth, 
networks in civil society crosscut power relations and 
hierarchies in the state, thwarting 
the dominance of any group or interest and providing an 
alternate means of representation. 
Finally, civil society provides a site for the discursive will 
formation that 
generates democratic legitimacy. 
Each of these claims rests on empirical foundations that 
might well be challenged. 
Most accounts of civil society, for instance, ignore such 
networks and associations as 
skinheads, neo-fascists and criminal gangs, raising serious 
questions about many of 
the claims just surveyed.30 Rosenblum warns that civil 
society is varied and complex, 
its moral and political effects difficult to discern and perhaps 
ultimately indeterminate 
thanks precisely to the immense variety and complexity of 
associational forms and 
activity. While this pluralism should be valued for its 
contribution to freedom, it 
should not be naively conflated with a logic of congruence 
that assumes the uniformity 
of associational life or the generalizability of its effects.31 
So far, moreover, 
hypotheses about civil society’s democratic effects have not 
been adequately 
tested, though Warren has clarified the myriad of claims and 
specified features of 
associations that might help us gauge their democratic 
effects.32 
Nonetheless, these empirical hypotheses are accepted 
provisionally so as to concentrate 
instead on some frequently overlooked assumptions about the 
relationship 
between the state and civil society on which the latter’s 
purported democratic functions 
and effects depend conceptually.33 The first assumption is that 
civil society 
and the state are coterminous. Civil society takes the state’s 
territory, jurisdiction 
and membership as its parameters. While the autonomous 
sphere of associational 
life occupies a distinct conceptual space, that space is delimited 
practically by the 
borders of the state. The members of civil society are simply 
the citizens of the 
state; the entire population is not necessarily included, or 
included equally, but 
when we talk about civil society in the United States, say, we 
accept implicitly that 
it does not include Mexican social movements or Canadian 
bowling leagues. Similarly, 
to the extent that we can talk about Canadian civil society, we 
acknowledge 
that it is coterminous with the Canadian state and its territory. 
Finally, civil society 
requires political authorities and institutions with jurisdiction 
within its territory 
6 DEMOCRATIZATION 
and over its members; it presumes some fit between the 
location of its activities and 
the location of state control or authority. In short, civil society 
on this model assumes 
a territorial state. This is hardly surprising; most modern 
political theory takes the 
state for granted.34 Still, this statist assumption is crucial in 
making sense of civil 
society’s democratic functions. 
Its significance is demonstrated through a second assumption – 
that there is 
‘democratic symmetry’ between civil society and the state. The 
state is the appropriate 
container of politics and vehicle for democracy; rightful rule 
attaches to a particular 
territory. As Held puts it, there is a ‘“natural community of fate” 
– a community 
which rightly governs itself and determines its own future’.35 
This symmetry is 
crucial to civil society’s role as a site for discursive will 
formation that guides or 
determines state policy and provides democratic legitimacy. 
Given that civil 
society is independent of the political sphere by definition, this 
function can only 
be democratic if there is an identity between civil society’s 
members and the 
state’s citizenry and if their will translates into law or policy 
only within the political 
community they share. To take a simplistic example, the 
implementation in Canadian 
law or policy of public opinion distilled through the serious, 
public-spirited deliberation 
of independent Mexican civic associations would not count as 
democratic. What 
matters is not merely the formation of public opinion according 
to norms of publicity 
and openness but also which public does the formulating. 
Conceiving civil society as 
a political community of fate reconciles the formation of public 
opinion and the 
generation of political demands with the necessary use of state 
power to enact or 
enable policies. The issue is less capacity than authority, the 
recognized and legitimate 
exercise of state power in a particular territory. This 
‘democratic symmetry’ 
simply but importantly reflects the foundation of the liberal-democratic 
state in the 
doctrine of popular sovereignty.36 
A third central assumption underpinning neo-Tocquevillian civil 
society’s democratic 
effects is that civil society and the state are mutually supportive and 
constitutive. 
37 The state’s laws structure civil society, defining its members’ rights and 
its civic spaces. The state’s institutions uphold the laws, regulating 
activities within 
civil society and guaranteeing rights;38 they are responsive to the 
demands of civil 
society, providing points of access and influence. The state’s norms shape 
civil 
society and the groups populating it; as Walzer puts it, ‘only a democratic 
state can 
create a democratic civil society, and only a democratic civil society can 
sustain 
a democratic state’.39 There is an obvious but instructive circularity here: 
the 
purported democratic functions and effects of civil society can only work in 
the 
context of a democratic state where participation, representation and 
deliberation 
are valued and institutionalized politically; only in these circumstances 
does civil 
society strengthen and support political democracy. This virtuous circle is 
the heart 
of the democratic case for civil society on the neo-Tocquevillian model. 
Identifying the interdependence of state and civil society in the neo- 
Tocquevillian 
model in no way constitutes a criticism; it simply makes explicit the 
assumptions 
upon which the model’s democratic claims depend. I acknowledge that 
both in principle 
and in practice associational life might manifest many of its salutary 
effects 
quite apart from the state – in large associations, in non-governmental 
institutions 
CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 7 
and in local communities of various kinds. Still, to reiterate, we cannot 
understand 
these effects to be ancillary to political democracy in the state – as 
champions of 
the neo-Tocquevillian model undoubtedly do – without understanding the 
interdependence 
of state and civil society on which they depend conceptually. 
Many (perhaps most) observers conceptualize GCS in neo-Tocquevillian 
fashion, 
emphasizing participation and trust-building through transnational 
networks, deliberation 
within global publics shaping norms and policy, representation of diverse 
global 
interests, demanding accountability from and providing a counterweight to 
global 
regimes, and so on.40 Certainly the constellation of transnational actors 
emphasized 
by proponents of GCS does in many respects resemble that in the neo- 
Tocquevillian 
model. Again, one might challenge the empirical hypotheses underlying 
these 
claims about the democratic effects of GCS.41 Instead, however, the 
intention 
here is to look at whether the assumptions underlying the purported 
democratic 
effects of civil society obtain at the supranational level. The aim is not to 
make an 
empirical assessment of GCS activity but rather to critique its democratic 
potential 
conceptually. 
Take the first assumption – that civil society and the state are 
coterminous. 
Clearly this assumption breaks down at the global level. There is no global 
polity, 
no political unit whose borders, institutions and membership correspond 
with those 
of a potential GCS. At least three important difficulties follow. The first 
concerns 
membership of GCS: is everyone an equal member whose voice and 
interests 
should always count equally on every issue and in every decision? Or, 
since global 
governance regimes have different jurisdictions and constituencies, are 
some boundaries 
implied? Is there one global public or many regional ones? How are these 
determinations 
made? Another difficulty has to do with the high degree of institutional 
differentiation among international governance organizations (IGOs). It is 
true that 
IGOs perform ‘state-like’ functions – regulation, enforcement, coordination 
and 
so on. But they are typically organized functionally rather than 
territorially, creating 
a patchwork of overlapping and fragmented jurisdictions that some 
writers liken 
to a ‘new medievalism’.42 The Westphalian state (at least mythically) 
established 
a unified authority and jurisdiction across all public functional domains. 
Progressive 
social change has historically depended upon this unity, upon a state 
possessing 
the authority to implement change throughout a society and its 
institutions; as Pasha 
and Blaney note, civil society itself often calls forth an expansion of the 
state apparatus 
as an agent of social reform.43 One of the key achievements of the 
post-war 
democratic welfare state was subordinating the capitalist economy to 
public – 
democratic – authority. Where key governance institutions are not 
unified or even 
coordinated, democratic purposes become difficult to achieve and 
maintain. 
Finally, despite talk of ‘new’ political spaces, the supranational 
associational 
sphere overlays political spaces in particular states; thus GCS is highly 
differentiated 
politically, with significant implications for its democratic character. 
When the WTO 
holds a ministerial meeting in Seattle, civil society is relatively free to 
organize and 
stage protests because Seattle is located in a democratic state with a 
functioning 
democratic civil society. Things look much different when the meeting 
moves 
to Doha – and this was of course the point in moving it there. The 
difference is 
8 DEMOCRATIZATION 
a function of accessibility, to be sure, but it is also immediately 
political: GCS is only 
as open or democratic as the political space (the state and civil 
society) in which it is 
manifest. Even users of the Internet – another new political space – 
must log on from 
somewhere, and the authorities there are showing an ever keener 
interest in what 
those users see and do. 
The second assumption, that the state and civil society share a 
democratic symmetry, 
also clearly does not hold at the supranational level. Democratic 
functions 
like representation of interests, participation, opinion formation and 
the balancing 
of competing interests all assume an institutionalized electoral 
connection that is 
clearly absent in GCS. The overlap between citizenship and 
membership in civil 
society at the state level means that each opinion is attached to a vote 
and thus 
carries weight with decision-makers. Since IGOs are unelected, this 
symmetry does 
not hold. Decision makers are not electorally accountable to 
constituents of GCS 
(except indirectly where democratically elected officials appoint 
them).44 Moreover, 
the asymmetry between IGOs and political communities of fate 
delegitimizes the 
democratic character of deliberation. Domestically, the state defines 
and delimits a 
demos, a self-governing political community; even if a global discourse 
could be 
truly open, inclusive, accessible and egalitarian – criteria which are 
utopian even 
in democratic states – it would lack democratic legitimacy precisely 
because it 
would not emanate from a political community previously 
acknowledged as legitimate 
by its members. 
Despite some heroic attempts to get around this problem, most 
notably by Held, 
there is no democratic way to define the demos; borders cannot in 
principle be drawn 
democratically because democracy presupposes the demos that takes 
decisions.45 
Some theorists have imagined that GCS might ‘bootstrap’ out of this 
difficulty, discursively 
constituting the democratic community its legitimacy takes for 
granted, 
but this circle cannot circumscribe the problems of plausibility it 
creates.46 Moreover,
without global political institutions to translate the public will 
into law and policy, it is 
not clear what the political meaning of global deliberations 
is or should be. Nor is it 
clear what would happen if the ‘global democratic will’ 
conflicted with the particular 
will of a democratic state.47 Given these difficulties, it 
becomes unclear what exactly 
the democratic functions of global opinion, discourse and 
deliberation might be.48 
Finally, the neo-Tocquevillian model presumes that civil 
society and the state are 
mutually constitutive. We have seen that a democratic civil 
society requires the rule 
of law as well as explicit guarantees of citizens’ rights; it 
requires norms of openness, 
freedom, equality and participation; and it requires 
institutions that are open to influence 
and scrutiny by the public. This is what Walzer meant by 
saying that ‘only 
a democratic state can create a democratic civil society’ 
(emphasis mine). In considering 
GCS as a model of global democracy, however, we must 
also consider whether 
only a democratic state can create a democratic civil 
society. Global governance is 
not characterized by the rule of law; at the global level 
there is no extensive legal 
system and few institutions to enforce those important laws 
that do exist. The 
rights possessed by members of GCS are their rights as 
citizens of particular states, 
and they vary tremendously. While governance regimes 
perform many state-like 
functions, they typically do not guarantee anyone’s rights 
(which is not to say they 
CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 9 
do not affect anyone’s rights). Moreover, while IGOs are 
responsible for much 
global governance, the absence of a global government 
means that a variety of 
other actors – from NGOs and TSMs to transnational 
corporations, organized crime, 
terrorist networks, private militias and sex traffickers – also 
exercises significant 
governance functions in the supranational domain. Many do 
not promote democracy 
locally, where they operate, or globally. States can – at 
least where they have the 
capacity – constrain the governance roles of such actors 
domestically, but their 
ability to do so supranationally is highly limited. Thus 
despite the exuberance of 
GCS advocates, non-state voluntary activity at the 
supranational level might on 
balance be detrimental to democratic norms; without a 
democratic state to support 
these norms and suppress non-democratic ones, a 
democratic GCSmight be impossible. 
In sum, GCS cannot support democracy in the way that 
neo-Tocquevillian civil 
society does because the latter’s democratic functions 
cannot work outside a democratic 
state. Empirically, GCS and domestic civil society are 
disanalogous in important ways; 
they describe different phenomena, and we have seen that 
those differences are directly 
relevant to the democratic role of civil society. 
Pragmatically, civil society strategies 
that help to reinforce democracy within the state – 
participation, deliberation and 
the like – lack the conceptual and institutional grounding on 
which their democratic 
functions and effects depend. Normatively, these differences 
raise important questions 
about the global applicability and relevance of the 
democratic ideal animating neo- 
Tocquevillian civil society. More on these problems below. 
The Anti-Authoritarian Model 
The anti-authoritarian model of civil society is best 
exemplified in the resistance and 
opposition politics of Latin America and Eastern Europe in 
the 1970s and 1980s.49 
This model of civil society has been described as 
‘antipolitics’, principled opposition 
to authoritarian regimes through individual and collective 
devotion to principles of 
civility, toleration, openness, human rights – in a word, 
democracy. Here civil 
society is not only separate from but also opposed to the state; 
it describes an 
ethical and political consciousness as well as the community of 
groups and individuals 
united in this consciousness.50 
The essence of the anti-authoritarian model, as the name 
suggests, is opposition to 
the ubiquitous and intrusive institutions of oppressive rule; it 
was an attempt to renew 
politics by freeing citizens from the ‘suffocating burden’ these 
institutions imposed.51 
On this understanding, ‘civil society was the name of the anti-authoritarian, 
anti-conformist 
impetus, rooted in the rediscovery of human rights and the 
possibility of non- 
Machiavellian politics’.52 It referred to the ‘autonomous space 
in society outside the 
purview of the totalitarian state and operating within the 
framework of democratic 
principles’.53 According to Gyo¨rgy Konrad, ‘antipolitics is the 
ethos of civil 
society, and civil society is the antithesis of military society’.54 
This ‘ethos’ has 
also been described as ‘a normative sense [denoting] a set of 
values having to do 
with democracy and freedom’.55 
As Va´clav Havel famously outlined in his essay ‘The Power of 
the Powerless’, 
dissent was the necessary first step in creating this ethos of 
resistance; it was 
10 DEMOCRATIZATION 
unavoidably a step to be taken by individuals deciding to ‘live 
within the truth’56 – 
roughly, to reject ideology and embrace intellectual honesty, 
personal integrity and a 
democratic ethic. Adam Michnik, one of the founders of 
Solidarity, similarly argued 
that if people began living as if they inhabited a free society 
their actions would in 
themselves inaugurate the creation of a free public space.57 
Such individual 
choices were nevertheless recognized as explicitly political, part 
of what Tismaneanu 
calls ‘the reinvention of politics outside the existing matrix of 
power’.58 Their political 
consequences would be ‘reflected in the constitution of 
structures that will derive 
from this new spirit, from human factors rather than from a 
particular formulation of 
political relationships and guarantees . . . The issue is the 
rehabilitation of values like 
trust, openness, responsibility, solidarity, love.’59 
Thus the goal was two-fold: the rehabilitation of ‘civil’ or ‘civic’ 
values,60 and the 
eventual creation of what another prominent Czech dissident, 
Va´ 
clav Benda, called ‘the 
parallel polis’ – a symbolic set of social, economic and political 
structures wholly separate 
from the state that might one day take over the state. The anti-political 
stance that 
followed from this democratic ethos animated the activities of 
groups like Solidarity 
and the Workers Defense Committee (KOR) in Poland and 
Charter 77 in Czechoslovakia. 
As Havel put it, ‘the point where living within the truth ceases 
to be a mere negation 
of living within a lie and becomes articulate in a particular way 
is the point at which 
something is born that might be called the “independent 
spiritual, social, and political 
life of society” ’.61 Still, as Goldfarb notes, ‘opposition to 
dictatorship does not necessarily 
lead to democracy’.62 Indeed, as Michnik and others saw, anti-politics 
can only 
offer evolutionism as a theory of democratization.63 
This transformative effort always had a crucial transnational 
dimension.64 The 
peace movements that operated on both sides of the Iron 
Curtain and the struggles 
for human rights in Eastern Europe and Latin America all relied 
on support, publicity 
and political pressure generated by transnational networks. This 
relationship is 
captured in the ‘spiral model’ developed by Risse and Sikkink, 
which explains how 
relatively weak social movements for human rights and democracy in 
authoritarian 
countries managed to have such profound transformative effects on 
entrenched and 
intransigent regimes.65 Dissident and opposition groups proved amazingly 
successful 
in highlighting governments’ failures to abide by their public commitments 
to democracy 
and human rights, undermining the governments’ credibility and domestic 
legitimacy 
and spurring diplomatic, economic and political pressure for change.66 
One can 
hardly make sense of democratization and redemocratization in Eastern 
Europe and 
Latin America without reference to the power of normative commitments 
to democracy 
and human rights and attention to the ways that these commitments were 
sustained and strengthened by transnational ties.67 
Civil society on the anti-authoritarian model aims to bring about 
democracy in 
the face of a hostile regime.68 Its democratic functions and effects are 
primarily transformational: 
it seeks the democratization of the regime in co-operation with 
transnational 
networks of supporters and the rehabilitation of society through the 
gradual 
creation of an independent social sphere of civility. On what assumptions 
do these 
strategies for democratization depend? Strangely enough, on the same 
assumptions 
as the democratic effects of neo-Tocquevillian civil society. First, while civil 
society 
CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 11 
functions in opposition to and often in spite of the state, it is still defined 
(conceptually and empirically) by its relation to the state. Civil society 
clearly 
aims at the transformation of a specific state and society – Czech, Polish, 
Argentinian – for renewal and rehabilitation. Resistance and opposition are 
directed 
toward a particular regime or state apparatus and rooted within the 
political and 
ethical community of a particular state society. Civil society seeks to 
create an autonomous 
sphere independent of the state’s intrusive ideology and bureaucracy, but 
its 
social boundaries and membership are still determined by the state. 
This link between civil society and a particular state is crucial to the 
strategy of 
democratization captured in the spiral model of Risse and Sikkink. These 
movements 
used traditional statist political measures – political, economic and 
diplomatic leverage 
– to press for the reform of authoritarian regimes. These strategies were 
effective 
because of the congruity between the targeted traditional states, with 
their discrete 
territories, economies and populations, and the democratic civil society 
movements 
within them. First, there was something definite to target and the means 
for doing 
so were well understood: transnational networks supporting local civil 
society 
movements took for granted and relied on the dynamics of realist politics 
in the 
Westphalian mould. Second, the objective was also well understood: to 
create a 
democratic regime on the social- or liberal-democratic model. Third, 
external 
pressure for change was motivated and justified in part by the sense that 
the targeted 
regime was neither representative of nor responsive to the will of its 
citizens. 
These points tie directly into the second, related assumption concerning 
the symmetry 
between civil society and the state. Although this symmetry is a pale echo 
of 
the democratic symmetry central to the neo-Tocquevillian model, the 
transformative 
aspirations of anti-authoritarian civil society still depend upon the same 
idea of a 
community of fate in which members of society are bound together in a 
shared 
political destiny. In addition to its role in justifying external pressure, this 
symmetry 
is manifest in the social solidarity underlying efforts to resist and 
ultimately remake 
the regime. The symmetry is clear in the political and ethical strategies of 
evolutionism, 
living in truth, and the parallel polis (itself never realized), which 
assert that state 
and society can be transformed through the rehabilitation of their 
constituent 
members and the institutions of their daily lives. This programme also 
represents a 
backhanded recognition of the mutually constitutive nature of state 
and civil 
society: its strategies indicate that not just the government but society 
itself was corrupted 
by the penetration of the state’s intrusive ideological and security 
apparatus.69 
The rehabilitation of society requires the rehabilitation of citizens as 
well as of their 
governing institutions. 
It is harder to assess democratic claims for GCS informed by the anti-authoritarian 
model. This is because the claims themselves are less clear; the model 
is underspeci-fied 
globally. Transnational networks do successfully use their moral 
authority to 
build support for local opposition groups, raise global awareness of 
certain issues 
and exert pressure on IGOs and world leaders. Still, these tactics and 
the victories 
won through them do not amount to a coherent programme for 
transforming global 
governance, much less to a framework for global democracy. Even if 
the number 
and success of such efforts could be increased dramatically they 
remain primarily 
12 DEMOCRATIZATION 
defensive and ad hoc in nature. Generalities like ‘global 
transformational politics’ and 
‘globalization from below’ might capture the spirit and aspirations of 
activists and 
scholars, but they provide few political prescriptions. This is not to 
denigrate these 
important efforts or to deny their connection to core democratic 
values; it is rather 
to note that they provide an incomplete model for democratizing global 
governance. 
Still, we can consider whether the strategies for democratization 
recommended by 
the anti-authoritarian model make sense supranationally given the 
assumptions on 
which they rest. The first strategy is that captured in the spiral model: 
transnational 
support for domestic opposition groups leading to positive 
transformation of the 
regime. Several problems arise in applying this strategy to global 
democratization. 
First, IGOs are not obviously susceptible to the same kinds of pressure 
as states. 
Practically, the close – if antagonistic – relationship between state and 
civil 
society on the domestic version of this model was a key factor in 
leveraging 
change. Because civil society aimed to transform a particular state, it 
could work 
with transnational allies to bring pressure on the state. Economic 
sanctions are effective 
against states (if at all) because they have relatively discrete economic 
systems 
that can be targeted; diplomatic and political sanctions are effective 
against states 
because to states such things matter crucially.70 None of these 
conditions applies to 
IGOs (at least not in the same way). They have no economies to 
punish, no diplomats 
to isolate. It is of course possible to pressure their officials and the 
governments who 
appoint them, but their intergovernmental nature significantly 
insulates IGOs from 
the heat of traditional pressure politics. Further, because global 
governance is 
highly differentiated – many regimes in many functional domains – 
bringing 
sustained and unified pressure on state governments to transform the 
system of 
governance (as opposed to changing policy) is difficult. 
These difficulties relate directly to a second cluster of problems with 
the transnational 
pressure strategy. At the state level, unified opposition was called 
forth by the 
common experience of systematic and pervasive oppression. This unity 
helped elicit
transnational support in part because it established a 
democratic impetus and justifi-cation 
for change. Global governance is more complex; 
diverse regimes affect differently 
situated people in very different ways, making democratic 
solidarity and claims 
about ‘democratic’ opposition difficult to assess. IGOs do 
not govern defined political 
communities; their rule is limited to particular functional 
domains. There is no political 
community of fate associated with this form of rule, making 
it less likely that 
democratic solidarity of the kind envisioned by the anti-authoritarian 
model could 
crystallize. Moreover, the disproportional influence of rich 
countries in most IGOs 
means that they often serve the interests of those countries 
and their citizens, 
making transnational solidarity problematic. This is not to 
deny that opposition to particular 
policies will sometimes be quite strong, especially where 
their implementation 
involves violations of human rights. But it is questionable 
whether such opposition 
qualifies as global democracy or a global movement for 
democratization. A politics 
of democratic opposition seems too simplistic for the 
complex realities of global 
governance today. 
The second major strategy associated with the anti-authoritarian 
model is rehabilitation, 
social and political transformation realized through 
individual ethical 
CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 13 
commitments. This strategy obviously depends on a high 
degree of symmetry 
between civil society and the state: Polish opposition groups 
aimed to transform 
the Polish state and Polish society. Much of the anti-authoritarian 
model’s democratic 
appeal comes from a faith in the political character of 
individual ethical acts; the hope 
is that these acts lead to social rehabilitation and renewal 
and, ultimately, to the 
regime’s transformation. This hope clearly requires and 
depends on a strong symmetry 
between civil society and the targeted regime; otherwise, 
individual actions 
could not precipitate political change. The mechanism of 
transformation envisioned 
here is tenuous even within states; the empirical link 
between ‘living in truth’ and 
regime change is uncertain, but at least involves creating an 
autonomous space for 
resistance. This mechanism seems improbable at the global 
level both because 
the links between individuals and specific IGOs are less 
direct and because lack of 
autonomous political space is not really the problem. 
The limits of these two strategies at the global level point to 
two more general 
difficulties with the anti-authoritarian model of GCS. First, 
the complexity of 
global governance makes it unclear what ‘regime’ and 
‘regime change’ might 
mean supranationally – especially since some IGOs, like the 
UNDP or the nascent 
ICC, support democratic norms. Total opposition and 
wholesale transformation 
seem inappropriately broad and strategically imprudent in 
this context. Second, 
given the transformational aims of the anti-authoritarian 
model, one might well ask 
transformation to what? The democratic function of the anti-authoritarian 
model is 
bringing about a liberal democracy. In the global context 
this puts the cart before 
the horse: it is profoundly unclear, as a brief survey of the 
literature indicates, what 
a democratic system of global governance might look like or 
what form it should 
take – a global state? a federation like the European Union? 
Being committed to 
democratic norms, as many agents in GCS no doubt are, is 
not the same as bringing 
about democracy. This is a much more vexing problem than 
advocates of democratizing 
global governance often appreciate, and it will be revisited 
shortly. 
To repeat, the article takes no position with respect to the 
value, importance or 
efficacy of transnational network and associational activity: 
these are not the questions 
with which the account is concerned. Yet it is not simply 
repeating cautionary 
statements about the uncertainty of GCS’s democratic effects. 
Instead the main proposition 
is that the purported democratic functions and effects of the 
two most commonly 
evoked models for GCS rest on assumptions that do not hold 
globally. This 
finding challenges the adequacy and propriety of these models 
as frameworks for 
thinking about global democracy and democratization – without 
prejudicing questions 
about the role of network and associational activity in creating 
and sustaining 
global democracy. 
Conclusion: The (Epistemological) Problem of Global Democracy 
My argument to this point can be summarized succinctly. The 
purported democratic 
functions and effects of domestic civil society models rely on 
statist assumptions 
about politics. These assumptions do not hold for supranational 
politics, undermining 
the democratic potential of GCS as a model for global 
democracy. This conclusion 
14 DEMOCRATIZATION 
argues that these failures reflect broader epistemological 
problems in the study of 
global politics, problems that, unless recognized and corrected, 
will continue to 
confuse our thinking about global democracy. 
Arguments proposing GCS as a model for global democracy 
exhibit what some 
theorists have called the ‘domestic fallacy’. This fallacy 
frequently appears in two 
interrelated misconceptions about global politics and 
democracy. The first is that 
the problem of global democracy is primarily a problem of size; 
the second, that 
supranational politics is fundamentally similar to domestic 
politics. These misconceptions 
lead to mistakes like those we have discovered in democratic 
arguments for 
GCS. One critic of GCS arguments has observed that 
The notion of civil society itself makes little sense apart from 
the notion of the 
state against which it was originally articulated as a form of 
politics contained 
within its boundaries, a form of domesticity, sometimes public 
and sometimes 
private, that depends first and foremost on the capacity of 
states to carve out the 
spatial domains necessary for any kind of politics worthy of the 
name to be 
constituted.71 
The domestic fallacy results from our frequent failure to 
recognize how deeply 
our thinking about politics is shaped by and embedded in the 
conceptual framework 
of the Westphalian state. Consider first the view that the 
problem of global democracy 
is primarily one of size. When we characterize the problem in 
terms of disjunctures, of 
a mismatch between an increasingly global politics and existing 
state-level democratic 
institutions, this view appears almost natural. Moreover, the 
solution to the 
problem, thus conceived, seems straightforward: we should 
‘super-size’ existing 
democratic institutions to ‘fit’ global politics. This is essentially 
the approach 
reflected in neo-Tocquevillian thinking about GCS, but it is also 
evident in cosmopolitan 
proposals for global assemblies and parliaments. 
Seeing the problem of global democracy as a problem of size 
invites two sorts of 
confusion. The first is confusion of the institutions through 
which democracy is realized 
with democracy itself. When we treat global democracy as a 
problem of size we 
tend to treat the familiar democratic institutions as ends rather 
than – as they should 
be regarded – means of translating democratic principles into practice.72 
The second 
and related confusion is treating the scale and reach of democratic 
institutions as 
unrelated to democracy’s meaning and purpose. The territorial limits of 
modern 
democratic institutions are not mere contingencies; they are directly 
related to 
democracy’s foundational normative assumptions concerning the demos 
and its 
sovereignty. Democratic institutions are located where they are in part 
thanks to historical 
contingencies, but this history itself informed the theorization of modern 
democracy.73 The idea of a people whose will is supreme within a 
particular territory 
and whose consent legitimizes government follows from the idea that 
states are 
natural and appropriate containers of politics – that is, from the idea of 
sovereignty. 
Democracy’s territorial institutions reflect this assumption; they are 
legitimate not 
because they are representative but because they represent an already 
constituted 
people in an already constituted political community. Thus it is impossible 
to 
change the scale or reach of democratic institutions without changing the 
meaning 
CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 15 
of democracy itself. Such conceptual connections get elided when 
democratic theorists 
view our role as one of transcribing existing models to the global context, 
finding 
plausible ways to make them fit or work globally.74 
Equally problematic is the assumption that global politics is fundamentally 
similar to domestic politics. The anti-authoritarian model illustrates several 
problems 
with this assumption, as we have seen, though again such problems apply 
to proposals 
for global parliaments and global deliberation as well. Consider here the 
example of 
so-called ‘new’ political spaces; despite the adjective, these spaces are 
treated as identical 
to traditional political spaces in terms of the politics that will fill them. But 
these 
spaces are really new. For one thing, they are politically layered: GCS, for 
instance, 
overlays already constituted political spaces without obliterating them. 
These two 
conceptual spaces coexist in one geographical space in ways that are 
unfamiliar 
and difficult to theorize. Traditional democratic theory is anchored in an 
exclusive 
political cartography (the sovereign state) that might be divided 
(public/private, 
family/civil, society/state) but is not multilayered.75 Concepts theorized 
for such a 
political space are not readily applied to the ‘new medievalism’ of 
overlapping jurisdictions 
and loyalties that typify global governance. Governance without 
government 
might aptly characterize supranational rule today; democracy without 
government is 
more difficult, precisely because modern democratic theory is in large part 
a theory 
of government. Since there is no supranational government, and since 
governance 
overlaps with and cuts across constituted governments, we have a new 
theoretical 
problem, not just a new instance of an old one. 
Put differently, it is not enough to modify the size or scope of familiar 
democratic 
institutions to accommodate new political spaces, overlapping jurisdictions 
and other 
such phenomena. To do so presumes their similarity to domestic 
phenomena by treating 
the problems they generate as problems of application, obfuscating how 
they 
impact the relevance and coherence of existing democratic models and 
concepts. 
To see this, consider accountability. It is a widely held view that making 
global 
governance regimes more accountable makes them more democratic (or 
even ‘democratizes’ 
them). This writer has nothing against accountability: he believes it is a 
good 
idea. But accountability to whom? To everyone? Or to those most affected 
by some 
issue? How does one determine who is most affected? How does one 
determine the 
criteria for making that determination? Who decides that question? 
The Westphalian 
state and the theory of sovereignty underlying it, whatever its 
empirical embarrassments, 
provided ready-made answers to such questions, answers modern 
democratic 
theory has incorporated at the most fundamental level in ideas like the 
demos and 
popular sovereignty. Accountability is democratic because it makes 
governance 
activities accountable to the right people; who they are is taken for 
granted. So 
accountability and similar notions are problematized by globalization 
not only 
because we become unsure to whom they pertain but also because, 
absent a settled 
conviction about this question, it is not clear that accountability 
remains democratic 
or even what ‘democratic’ might mean. These are not merely abstract 
problems. How 
does global accountability square with the continued responsiveness of 
state-level 
democracy to its people? Do citizens of rich democracies really want 
the IGOs 
currently administering the world order in their favour to instead treat 
the concerns 
16 DEMOCRATIZATION 
of everyone equally? On what democratic basis could they object to 
such an 
arrangement – other than one that reasserted the democratic primacy 
of the national 
community of fate? 
Critics might object here that the argument is guilty of the very 
mistake that has 
been ascribed to GCS theories – and that the writer has missed his 
own point. Part 
of the appeal of proposals for a democratic GCS is that they help us 
escape this 
Westphalian mindset. By emphasizing that democracy has worked in a 
certain way 
within the state, these critics might assert, the author reinforces the 
view that it 
cannot work apart from the state. The author has missed, the critics 
might continue, 
that GCS is precisely a way of conceiving how democracy might work 
outside the 
state, how it might be deepened and extended into new and emerging 
domains of 
governance. His position seems to imply that democracy does require 
a demos, 
traditional parliamentary institutions and the other familiar trappings 
of the state 
and dynamics of state politics. 
However, the article’s criticism of GCS theories is not that they fail to 
appreciate 
that democracy can only be realized within the state; on the contrary, 
the author shares 
a commitment to finding ways to realize democracy globally.76 But 
democracy as we 
understand it today was theorized and implemented within the modern 
state, with two 
important implications. First, these models cannot simply be applied to 
global politics 
without careful consideration of whether their democratic functions and 
effects can be 
realized in that context. While GCS theories have been the focus here, 
many theories 
of global democracy also neglect this important question. Second – 
and here is where 
the imagined objection to the article breaks down – we cannot assume 
that extricating 
the concept of democracy from the context in which it was theorized 
and institutionalized 
leaves its meaning intact. Our understanding of what democracy is – 
never 
mind how it works – is so deeply tied up with its realization in the 
Westphalian 
state that we must seriously reconsider even our most basic intuitions 
about what it 
might mean apart from that context. 
The point is not that there can be no democracy without a demos or a 
parliament; it 
is instead that we have very little sense of what democracy means 
once these concepts 
and institutions cease to correspond with political regularities in the 
familiar way.
Even seemingly unobjectionable notions like accountability 
prove unreliable and 
potentially misleading guides to cogent thinking about 
global democracy. We need 
a theory of global democracy, not just the application of 
existing democratic theory 
to the global context. And we need it urgently, to provide an 
alternative to the increasingly 
dominant and anti-democratic logic of neo-liberalism driving 
contemporary 
globalization.77 It is crucial to step back and reconsider 
democracy’s core values, 
its fundamental principles and commitments, and rethink 
what they might mean 
once removed from the conceptual framework of the 
modern state. Only then will 
it be possible to make reliable judgements about how we 
might pursue democratization 
and realize democratic values. Social movements uniting 
people around the globe 
in a shared commitment to democratic norms will form an 
important part of this 
pursuit, and the activities of many networks and 
movements today perform a vital 
function in keeping the power and promise of that 
commitment plainly before us. 
As students of democracy, however, we must avoid the 
temptation to confuse the 
CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 17 
democratic potentialities of such activity with global 
democracy. The most difficult 
problem of global democracy lies in determining what it 
might be. But, unavoidably, 
it is with that problem that we must begin. 
Civil society is composed of the totality of voluntary civic 
and social organizations and institutions that form the basis 
of a functioning society as opposed to the force-backed 
structures of a state (regardless of that state's political 
system) and commercial institutions. 
Origin 
The term is often traced to Adam Ferguson, who saw the 
development of a "commercial state" as a way to change 
the corrupt feudal order and strengthen the liberty of the 
individual.[1] While Ferguson did not draw a line between 
the state and the society, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, a 
German philosopher, made this distinction in his Elements 
of the Philosophy of Right [2]. In this work, civil society 
(Hegel used the term "buergerliche Gesellschaft" though it 
is now referred to as Zivilgesellschaft in German to 
emphasize a more inclusive community) was a stage on the 
dialectical relationship between Hegel's perceived opposites, 
the macro-community of the state and the micro-community 
of the family [3]. Broadly speaking, the term 
was split, like Hegel's followers, to the political left and 
right. On the left, it became the foundation for Karl Marx's 
bourgeois society [4]; to the right it became a description 
for all non-state aspects of society, expanding out of the 
economic rigidity of Marxism into culture, society and 
politics [5] 
Definition 
There are myriad definitions of civil society. The London 
School of Economics Centre for Civil Society working 
definition is illustrative: 
Civil society refers to the arena of uncoerced collective 
action around shared interests, purposes and values. In 
theory, its institutional forms are distinct from those of the 
state, family and market, though in practice, the boundaries 
between state, civil society, family and market are often 
complex, blurred and negotiated. Civil society commonly 
embraces a diversity of spaces, actors and institutional 
forms, varying in their degree of formality, autonomy and 
power. Civil societies are often populated by organisations 
such as registered charities, development non-governmental 
organisations, community groups, women's 
organisations, faith-based organisations, professional 
associations, trade unions, self-help groups, social 
movements, business associations, coalitions and advocacy 
groups.[6] 
Civil society and democracy 
The literature on links between civil society and democracy 
have their root in early liberal writings like those of 
Tocqueville. However they were developed in significant 
ways by 20th century theorists like Gabriel Almond and 
Sidney Verba, who identified the role of civil society in a 
democratic order as vital [7]. 
They argued that the political element of many civil society 
organisations facilitates better awareness and a more 
informed citizenry, who make better voting choices, 
participate in politics, and hold government more accountable 
as a result [8]. The statutes of these organizations have often 
been considered micro-constitutions because they accustom 
participants to the formalities of democratic decision making. 
More recently, Robert Putnam has argued that even non-political 
organisations in civil society are vital for democracy. 
This is because they build social capital, trust and shared 
values, which are transferred into the political sphere and help 
to hold society together, facilitating an understanding of the 
interconnectedness of society and interests within it 
Others, however, have questioned how democratic civil society 
actually is. Some have noted that the civil society actors have 
now obtained a remarkable amount of political power without 
anyone directly electing or appointing them [10]. Finally, other 
scholars have argued that, since the concept of civil society is 
closely related to democracy and representation, it should in 
turn be linked with ideas of nationality and nationalism [11]. 
Civil society and globalization: Global Civil Society 
The term civil society is currently often used by critics and 
activists as a reference to sources of resistance to and the 
domain of social life which needs to be protected against 
globalization. This is because it is seen as acting beyond 
boundaries and across different territories [12]. However, as 
civil society can, under many definitions, include and be funded 
and directed by those businesses and institutions (especially 
donors linked to European and Northern states) who support 
globalization, this is a contested use [13]. 
On the other hand, others see globalization as a social 
phenomenon bringing classical liberal values which inevitably 
lead to a larger role for civil society at the expense of politically 
derived state institutions. 
Civil Society's Responses to Globalization 
By Candido Grzybowski 
Corporate Watch 
November 8, 1995 
There is no worse slavery than to be deprived of our ability to 
think, create, and dare in freedom. There is no greater 
domination than an imposed way of thinking that cannot be 
challenged. Nothing is more tragic than to be limited by visions, 
desires and justifications presented to us as inevitable. 
Globalization is more than a process in human history; it seems 
to be and to act as a prison for hearts and minds, thoughts and 
movements. The dominant form of globalization appears as the 
only way out that nothing could oppose. We are told that 
anyone who does not adjust to this fate will perish. At least, 
this is how the concept of globalization has been disseminated 
by governments, businesspeople, financiers - or their 
ideologues. 
We must rebel against this way of thinking. Planetary 
citizenship requires nonconformist thought and action. The first 
response to globalization is to acknowledge that it was 
produced by us, by human beings. It is not a monster to rule 
over us, but a human invention, with its limitations and 
possibilities like our own life condition. We must use a different 
approach to think about globalization, taking alternative 
globalizations into consideration. For this, the conventional 
hegemonic way of thinking dictated by neoliberalism and by 
"free market" consensus is not very helpful. It is necessary that 
we, as citizens of the planet earth committed to democracy, 
build our own agenda, our own way of viewing issues and 
tasks, our own priorities. We can't ignore other approaches and 
their proposals, but let's not limit ourselves to them. Let's face 
up to them! 
Several globalizations, different responses 
Dominant forms of globalization are powered by an 
unrestrained drive to maximize profits. Open the borders, 
reduce and privatize the state, deregulate, be efficient and 
competitive, submit everything and everybody to savage free 
market law - such are the rules and basic principles of key 
economic globalization actors. In practice, global speculation 
was installed - a global casino. Productive structures and 
processes are increasingly more distanced from human 
development needs. Such globalization entails huge economic 
instability and political crisis. It is deeply destructive and 
antihuman. Never before has social inequality and exclusion 
reached such levels - too many human beings for an economy 
meant for less people, pursuing an unsustainable pattern of 
resource-use and consumption. Without borders, apartheid 
becomes global. 
In the face of this exclusionary globalization, we need to look at 
other globalizations. Some of them bear alternatives and 
hopes. In the struggle against globalization serving only 
business interests, actors emerge who are forging the bases of 
a planetary civil society founded on human rights and active 
citizenship. However, fundamentalisms of all sorts also 
proliferate in civil societies, propagating intolerance and 
violence. They destroy and exclude in their own ways. The key 
is that ongoing processes are challenging the world power system formed 
in the past. National states have been weakened and have been losing 
their regulatory capacity over economic forces active on a world scale. 
However, multilateral agencies are still deeply influenced by their origins 
and need many changes to confront challenges posed by globalization 
processes. 
In fact, the break with a bipolar world - with its hegemonic models and 
peripheries - does not just signal the victory of one pole over the other. It 
aggravates world contrasts within each particular society and within all 
humanity . However different we find ourselves, our destiny is also 
connected to others. Globalization processes do not remove us from where 
we live, from our culture, nation, or religion. They simply change the 
bases and perspectives of our lives, of our way of thinking and acting. 
Because our localized action can have substantial global impact, global 
dynamics - operating outside our control - redefines the possibilities and 
limits of what we do at a local level. More than ever we must "think 
globally and act locally." We live amidst very confusing proposals and 
concrete struggles. More than a new world order, we witness an extremely 
contradictory process of destruction and construction of a new civilization. 
Humanity goes through a period of uncertainties, lack of definitions, and 
absence of great utopian projects pointing the way forward. The task is 
precisely to rebuild such projects on new bases. We need to put forward 
globalization alternatives that could subject the market and state power to 
world citizens' demands. 
Priority task: strengthen civil society's democratic outlook 
Fundamental changes in humankind's history may occur along with 
economic or power changes. However, this doesn't imply that economic 
and power change should be the exclusive and priority focus of the 
strategy for change and for building a different globalization. Rather, it is 
a necessary, but not sufficient condition. After all, who makes up the 
economy and state power? Genetically, we ourselves do. The very human 
condition of living in society leads us to invent economic and power 
structures. Neither economies nor states create civil societies, just the 
opposite. With this approach, I have to acknowledge that civil society's 
most strategic and fundamental response to globalization is to reinvent 
itself. Civil societies must view themselves in the framework of 
globalization, enabling each inhabitant to think about himself or herself as 
a member of the same planet earth. Above all, we members of civil 
societies must redefine ourselves as citizens of a globalized world. This is 
a greater task than would appear at first sight. 
In fact, I'm saying that cultural change within civil society is an 
indispensable condition for changing the economy and markets, as well as 
power and state. I understand cultural change as change in ways of 
thinking and doing by different social actors making up a given society in 
a determined historical framework. Fortunately, this is not a vague and 
distant concept, but something concrete within everyone's reach. I'm 
referring to real processes in our societies and at the international level 
which merit and should have our attention here and now. Identifying such 
processes, acting on them, and maximizing their democratizing 
possibilities is our most urgent priority. 
I will mention some clear-cut examples. The environmental movement has 
a potential for cultural change that I want to emphasize. Today we view 
our relationship with nature in a radically different way. This results from 
an approach to environmental degradation and to challenges posed by 
sustainability forged by certain citizens' groups in concrete and specific 
situations. Their capacity to identify issues, formulate proposals, and 
mobilize - thus creating the first large global movement - has become one 
of the most insurmountable barriers to economic globalization. Raising 
awareness, public debate, and concrete action against corporations and 
governments has created the possibility of re-thinking the development 
model itself. Is this enough? No, but without the environmental 
movement, civil society would be deprived of a fundamental instrument to 
come to grips with globalization imposed by free-market apologists. Still 
on the ecological movement, it's important to note how it interconnects 
global and local aspects. I can cite the example of Brazil's rubber-tappers 
and forest peoples. They have mobilized and started fighting to defend 
their immediate living and working conditions threatened by forest 
destruction to create pastures and set up large farming and cattle-raising 
projects. Ecological groups throughout the world have identified the global 
dimension in their struggle as an alternative to environmental destruction 
carried out by prevailing economic processes. The symbolic character of 
this struggle internationalized it and the murder of Chico Mendes was 
perceived as an assault upon planetary citizenry. 
Using the same approach, the feminist movement is rethinking gender 
relations and the women's condition throughout the world. The past 
twenty years, culminating in the recent Beijing conference, has witnessed 
the emergence of an issue that remains one of civil society's greatest 
challenges. After all, both the problem and its solution are found in civil 
society before new power and production relationships materialize. We are 
facing a process of cultural change in gender relations, barely underway, 
but indispensable to radical change and effective democratization of 
human societies. The extremely diverse process already underway in civil 
societies throughout the planet bears great potentialities for building 
another kind of globalization. 
I'm citing these examples to show the importance of change in civil 
society itself, as a precondition for other forms of globalization. I should 
also acknowledge the existence within civil societies of great obstacles and 
limiting forces to the alternative of global democratization. Religiously 
and/or ethnically-inspired fundamentalist movements have prospered 
because they attract followers and activists in our own societies. It's 
not cultural diversity that explains fundamentalism's destructive 
potential to create violence and social exclusion. On the contrary, non-acceptance 
of equality in diversity leads to isolation, fragmentation, 
and intolerance. It's in the hands of civil society's groups to build 
conditions to defy fundamentalism as a world vision and to confront its 
destructive practices. Above all, it's a confrontation among citizens. 
Israeli Prime Minister's recent murder in the conflict-ridden Middle East 
reveals the nature of the fundamentalist problem. 
However, our civil societies face great challenges on the issue of 
poverty and social exclusion. Globalization processes may also be seen 
to unveil and deepen the logic of inequality and exclusion in the world. 
Sparing no society, poverty and destitution are now global 
phenomena. Worse still, there is a radical separation between 
economic and social spheres - while economies are globalized, the 
social is nationalized. The greatest indicator of the narrow limits of 
economic globalization is increasing control over migration. All barriers 
to circulation of goods are lifted but their producers are blocked from 
moving freely! In addition, visions and wills are forged within societies 
to exclude foreign workers, denying them basic citizenship rights. 
These are globalization's contrasts and dead ends. 
In Brazil we have a movement that is particularly eloquent in showing 
potentialities for cultural change, forged by civil society itself around 
the issue of social exclusion and poverty. It has a universal dimension 
despite its unique Brazilian features. It joins with other similar 
movements throughout the world and contributes in its own way to 
forging a new way of thinking and acting by groups of civil society 
relating to business and government. After all, it appeals to citizens' 
consciousness and action as the basis for change. We are referring to 
the movement "Citizens' Action Against Hunger, Poverty, and for Life" 
(Citizens' Action). Since March 1993, Citizens' Action has, through 
successive mobilizations, forced society to look introspectively for 
ideas and energy to launch a process to alter the country's hunger and 
poverty situation. This article is not the place to describe that civic 
movement. It just draws attentions to its nature. The movement is a 
learning process for the citizenry based on ethical indignation. Citizens' 
Action was not created to remind the poor and the hungry that they 
are responsible for their own fate. This movement directs itself to 
those with means, to those integrated in the current development 
model, to enable them to see the others and assume responsibility as 
citizens for their fate. Thus, basic values of human togetherness, the 
foundation of democracy, are recovered. It's not a matter of struggling 
for one's own rights, but for citizenship rights denied to the hungry, 
the destitute, and the excluded of all sorts. Denying the citizenship of 
others limits ours. Democracy and misery are ethically incompatible. 
In Citizens' Action there is no denying the importance of the state, 
governments and their policies, nor corporations' social responsibility. 
However, we seek the catapult for change that comes from citizens 
changing their attitudes when confronted with this issue. They can, in 
a sovereign way and without asking anyone's opinion, invent, take 
initiatives, organize decentralized committees - without duplicating 
models. They can mobilize forces and resources, promote 
partnerships, and contribute their share. Such actions create the 
atmosphere for a political and cultural movement favoring change. The 
lesson to draw from Brazil's Citizens' Action is that the potential in civil 
society for change is huge and decisive but needs to be primed. 
A question worth noticing is the emergence of ethics in civil societies' 
response to the neoliberal outlook and its globalization proposals. Mere 
defense of a human society based on free market laws condemns us to 
barbarism. Its destructive social and ecological potential results from 
denying primacy to values or to ethical considerations in relationships 
between human beings and between peoples. Even worse, this is a 
cynical way of thinking because it denies any possibility of an 
alternative approach. Dubbing itself as modern, this deeply 
conservative thinking invites each society in particular and the 
planetary society under construction to renounce the possibility of 
advancing civilization. Neoliberal thought is authoritarian and 
technocratic, prioritizing the economy to the detriment of politics and 
culture. Humankind had to struggle and suffer to identify and uphold 
values and rights whose central role is now negated by this narrow-minded 
utilitarianism. To see beyond the neoliberal wave and re-affirm 
the primacy of ethics and human beings is one of the greatest 
challenges for humanists and democrats on the threshold of the XXI 
Century. 
Forging another kind of globalization within civil society is possible. To 
do that we must re-affirm the primacy of the ethical principles 
constituting democracy: equality, freedom, participation, and human 
diversity and solidarity. They are capable of touching the hearts and 
minds of civil society's different groups and sectors. These principles 
should regulate power and market and be upheld and practiced 
throughout the world. The priority task is to counterpose a deepening 
process of global democracy and of planetary-scale cultural change to 
worldwide neoliberal disorder. 
A viable strategy: combining social mobilization and political pressure 
Having explained that the basic proposal is viable, let's tentatively 
discuss the strategy as a whole. We live in a concrete world, within
time and space, with ongoing real processes. We want to 
shape globalization taking into account that it may open 
new possibilities for humankind. This is not only desirable 
but necessary. But how can civil society redirect 
globalization's course? The strategy I propose is to prioritize 
ways of viewing and thinking - the prevailing attitudes and 
values within civil societies themselves concerning 
globalization. Perceptions and proposals of different civic 
groups, their movements and large mobilizations are forged 
in political and cultural confrontation and through action and 
public debate. To get the other side of the proposal to work 
- pressure, lobbying, and demands on governments, 
multilateral agencies and corporations - it is necessary to 
create a favorable atmosphere for linkages and networks 
within civil society, at both the national and international 
level. 
This is not the place to analyze the ample openings for 
political action by different actors in the planetary civil 
society being built today. We all have shown already that, 
when based on concrete local mobilizations, our intervention 
in negotiating forums such as large international 
conferences changes the quality of negotiations, both in 
their content and in the type of commitments governments 
undertake in those events. We also realize that conferences 
are only a starting point. Carrying out action plans requires 
new pressures and lobbying efforts. Again, broader 
engagement of different social sectors and a favorable 
atmosphere become decisive factors. 
Therefore, our strategy must combine actions and proposals 
to strengthen and mobilize civil society, and efforts to urge 
governments and multilateral agencies to take the pathway 
already indicated on the international agenda. The official 
agenda should not set the limits of our action. We need to 
expand our independent spaces for political action, with our 
own agenda, even at the international level. NGO and social 
movements' conferences, debates, forums, and networks 
(including computer networks) should help in the task of 
emancipating societies, of providing them with autonomy 
and capacity for exercising their role. In formulating 
globalization proposals we must free ourselves from narrow 
national and local outlooks and from the hegemony of 
governments, multilateral agencies, large corporations and 
finance capital. Although we don't shy away from this arena 
of struggle, the possibility of our intervention at this level 
does not only depend on competence and creativity. Above 
all, political action to confront the power system and the 
market for a democratic globalization presupposes 
strengthening our civil societies. Our challenge is to 
combine both poles. This confrontation will certainly shape a 
different globalization. 
CHAPTER 2 
THE FIVE STAGES-OF-GROWTH--A SUMMARY 
It is possible to identify all societies, in their economic 
dimensions, as lying within one of five categories: the 
traditional society, the preconditions for take-off, the take-off, 
the drive to maturity, and the age of high mass-consumption. 
THE TRADITIONAL SOCIETY 
First, the traditional society. A traditional society is one 
whose structure is developed within limited production 
functions, based on pre-Newtonian science and technology, 
and on pre-Newtonian attitudes towards the physical world. 
Newton is here used as a symbol for that watershed in 
history when men came widely to believe that the external 
world was subject to a few knowable laws, and was 
systematically capable of productive manipulation. 
The conception of the traditional society is, however, in no 
sense static; and it would not exclude increases in output. 
Acreage could be expanded; some ad hoc technical 
innovations, often highly productive innovations, could be 
introduced in trade, industry and agriculture; productivity 
could rise with, for example, the improvement of irrigation 
works or the discovery and diffusion of a new crop. But the 
central fact about the traditional society was that a ceiling 
existed on the level of attainable output per head. This 
ceiling resulted from the fact that the potentialities which 
flow from modern science and technology were either not 
available or not regularly and systematically applied. 
Both in the longer past and in recent times the story of 
traditional societies was thus a story of endless change. The 
area and volume of trade within them and between them 
fluctuated, for example, with the degree of political and 
social turbulence, the efficiency of central rule, the upkeep 
of the roads. Population--and, within limits, the level of 
life--rose and fell not only with the sequence of the 
harvests, but with the incidence of war and of plague. 
Varying degrees of manufacture developed; but, as in 
agriculture, the level of productivity was limited by the 
inaccessibility of modern science, its applications, and its frame 
of mind. 
Generally speaking, these societies, because of the limitation on 
productivity, had to devote a very high proportion of their 
resources to agriculture; and flowing from the agricultural 
system there was an hierarchical social structure, with 
relatively narrow scope--but some scope--for vertical mobility. 
Family and clan connexions played a large role in social 
organization. The value system of these societies was generally 
geared to what might be called a long-run fatalism; that is, the 
assumption that the range of possibilities open to one's 
grandchildren would be just about what it had been for one's 
grandparents. But this long-run fatalism by no means excluded 
the short-run option that, within a considerable range, it was 
possible and legitimate for the individual to strive to improve 
his lot, within his lifetime. In Chinese villages, for example, 
there was an endless struggle to acquire or to avoid losing land, 
yielding a situation where land rarely remained within the same 
family for a century. 
Although central political rule--in one form or another--often 
existed in traditional societies, transcending the relatively self-sufficient 
regions, the centre of gravity of political power 
generally lay in the regions, in the hands of those who owned 
or controlled the land. The landowner maintained fluctuating 
but usually profound influence over such central political power 
as existed, backed by its entourage of civil servants and 
soldiers, imbued with attitudes and controlled by interests 
transcending the regions. 
In terms of history then, with the phrase 'traditional society' we 
are grouping the whole pre-Newtonian world : the dynasties in 
China; the civilization of the Middle East and the 
Mediterranean; the world of medieval Europe. And to them we 
add the post-Newtonian societies which, for a time, remained 
untouched or unmoved by man's new capability for regularly 
manipulating his environment to his economic advantage. 
To place these infinitely various, changing societies in a single 
category, on the ground that they all shared a ceiling on the 
productivity of their economic techniques, is to say very little 
indeed. But we are, after all, merely clearing the way in order 
to get at the subject of this book; that is, the post-traditional 
societies, in which each of the major characteristics of the 
traditional society was altered in such ways as to permit regular 
growth: its politics, social structure, and (to a degree) its 
values, as well as its economy. 
THE PRECONDITIONS FOR TAKE-OFF 
The second stage of growth embraces societies in the process 
of transition; that is, the period when the preconditions for 
take-off are developed; for it takes time to transform a 
traditional society in the ways necessary for it to exploit the 
fruits of modern science, to fend off diminishing returns, and 
thus to enjoy the blessings and choices opened up by the 
march of compound interest. 
The preconditions for take-off were initially developed, in a 
clearly marked way, in Western Europe of the late seventeenth 
and early eighteenth centuries as the insights of modern 
science began to be translated into new production functions in 
both agriculture and industry, in a setting given dynamism by 
the lateral expansion of world markets and the international 
competition for them. But all that lies behind the break-up of 
the Middle Ages is relevant to the creation of the preconditions 
for take-off in Western Europe. Among the Western European 
states, Britain, favoured by geography, natural resources, 
trading possibilities, social and political structure, was the first 
to develop fully the preconditions for take-off. 
The more general case in modern history, however, saw the 
stage of preconditions arise not endogenously but from some 
external intrusion by more advanced societies. These invasions-literal 
or figurative-shocked the traditional society and began or 
hastened its undoing; but they also set in motion ideas and 
sentiments which initiated the process by which a modern 
alternative to the traditional society was constructed out of the 
old culture. 
The idea spreads not merely that economic progress is possible, 
hut that economic progress is a necessary condition for some 
other purpose, judged to be good: be it national dignity, private 
profit, the general welfare, or a better life for the children. 
Education, for some at least, broadens and changes to suit the 
needs of modern economic activity. New types of enterprising 
men come forward--in the private economy, in government, or 
both--willing to mobilize savings and to take risks in pursuit of 
profit or modernization. Banks and other institutions for 
mobilizing capital appear. Investment increases, notably in 
transport, communications, and in raw materials in which other 
nations may have an economic interest. The scope of 
commerce, internal and external, widens. And, here and there, 
modern manufacturing enterprise appears, using the new 
methods. But all this activity proceeds at a limited pace within 
an economy and a society still mainly characterized by 
traditional low-productivity methods, by the old social structure and 
values, and by the regionally based political institutions that developed in 
conjunction with them. 
In many recent cases, for example, the traditional society persisted side 
by side with modern economic activities, conducted for limited economic 
purposes by a colonial or quasi-colonial power. 
Although the period of transition--between the traditional society and the 
take-off--saw major changes in both the economy itself and in the balance 
of social values, a decisive feature was often political. Politically, the 
building of an effective centralized national state--on the basis of 
coalitions touched with a new nationalism, in opposition to the traditional 
landed regional interests, the colonial power, or both, was a decisive 
aspect of the preconditions period; and it was, almost universally, a 
necessary condition for take-off. 
There is a great deal more that needs to be said about the preconditions 
period, but we shall leave it for chapter 3, where the anatomy of the 
transition from a traditional to a modern society is examined. 
THE TAKE-OFF 
We come now to the great watershed in the life of modern societies: the 
third stage in this sequence, the take-off. The take-off is the interval when 
the old blocks and resistances to steady growth are finally overcome. The 
forces making for economic progress, which yielded limited bursts and 
enclaves of modern activity, expand and come to dominate the society. 
Growth becomes its normal condition. Compound interest becomes built, 
as it were, into its habits and institutional structure. 
In Britain and the well-endowed parts of the world populated substantially 
from Britain (the United States, Canada etc.) the proximate stimulus for 
take-off was mainly (but not wholly) technological. In the more general 
case, the take-off awaited not only the build-up of social overhead capital 
and a surge of technological development in industry and agriculture, but 
also the emergence to political power of a group prepared to regard the 
modernization of the economy as serious, high-order political business. 
During the take-off, the rate of effective investment and savings may rise 
from, say, 5 % of the national income to 10% or more; although where 
heavy social overhead capital investment was required to create the 
technical preconditions for take-off the investment rate in the 
preconditions period could be higher than 5%, as, for example, in Canada 
before the 1890's and Argentina before 1914. In such cases capital 
imports usually formed a high proportion of total investment in the 
preconditions period and sometimes even during the take-off itself, as in 
Russia and Canada during their pre-1914 railway booms. 
During the take-off new industries expand rapidly, yielding profits a large 
proportion of which are reinvested in new plant; and these new industries, 
in turn, stimulate, through their rapidly expanding requirement for factory 
workers, the services to support them, and for other manufactured goods, 
a further expansion in urban areas and in other modern industrial plants. 
The whole process of expansion in the modern sector yields an increase of 
income in the hands of those who not only save at high rates but place 
their savings at the disposal of those engaged in modern sector activities. 
The new class of entrepreneurs expands; and it directs the enlarging flows 
of investment in the private sector. The economy exploits hitherto unused 
natural resources and methods of production. 
New techniques spread in agriculture as well as industry, as agriculture is 
commercialized, and increasing numbers of farmers are prepared to 
accept the new methods and the deep changes they bring to ways of life. 
The revolutionary changes in agricultural productivity are an essential 
condition for successful take-off; for modernization of a society increases 
radically its bill for agricultural products. In a decade or two both the basic 
structure of the economy and the social and political structure of the 
society are transformed in such a way that a steady rate of growth can be, 
thereafter, regularly sustained. 
As indicated in chapter 4, one can approximately allocate the take-off of 
Britain to the two decades after 1783; France and the United States to the 
several decades preceding 1860; Germany, the third quarter of the 
nineteenth century; Japan, the fourth quarter of the nineteenth century; 
Russia and Canada the quarter-century or so preceding 1914; while 
during the 1950's India and China have, in quite different ways, launched 
their respective take-offs. 
THE DRIVE TO MATURITY 
After take-off there follows a long interval of sustained if fluctuating 
progress, as the now regularly growing economy drives to extend modern 
technology over the whole front of its economic activity. Some 10-20% of 
the national income is steadily invested, permitting output regularly to 
outstrip the increase in population. The make-up of the economy changes 
unceasingly as technique improves, new industries accelerate, older 
industries level off. The economy finds its place in the international 
economy: goods formerly imported are produced at home; new import 
requirements develop, and new export commodities to match them. The 
society makes such terms as it will with the requirements of modern 
efficient production, balancing off the new against the older values and 
institutions, or revising the latter in such ways as to support rather than to 
retard the growth process. 
Some sixty years after take-off begins (say, forty years after the end of 
take-off) what may be called maturity is generally attained. The economy, 
focused during the take-off around a relatively narrow complex of industry 
and technology, has extended its range into more refined and 
technologically often more complex processes; for example, there may be 
a shift in focus from the coal, iron, and heavy engineering industries of the 
railway phase to machine-tools, chemicals, and electrical equipment. 
This, for example, was the transition through which Germany, Britain, 
France, and the United States had passed by the end of the nineteenth 
century or shortly thereafter. But there are other sectoral patterns 
which have been followed in the sequence from take-off to maturity, 
which are considered in chapter 5. 
Formally, we can define maturity as the stage in which an economy 
demonstrates the capacity to move beyond the original industries 
which powered its take-off and to absorb and to apply efficiently over 
a very wide range of its resources--if not the whole range--the most 
advanced fruits of (then) modern technology. This is the stage in 
which an economy demonstrates that it has the technological and 
entrepreneurial skills to produce not everything, but anything that it 
chooses to produce. It may lack (like contemporary Sweden and 
Switzerland, for example) the raw materials or other supply conditions 
required to produce a given type of output economically; but its 
dependence is a matter of economic choice or political priority rather 
than a technological or institutional necessity. 
Historically, it would appear that something like sixty years was 
required to move a society from the beginning of take-off to maturity. 
Analytically the explanation for some such interval may lie in the 
powerful arithmetic of compound interest applied to the capital stock, 
combined with the broader consequences for a society's ability to 
absorb modern technology of three successive generations living under 
a regime where growth is the normal condition. But, clearly, no 
dogmatism is justified about the exact length of the interval from take-off 
to maturity. 
THE AGE OF HIGH MASS-CONSUMPTION 
We come now to the age of high mass-consumption, where, in time, 
the leading sectors shift towards durable consumers' goods and 
services: a phase from which Americans are beginning to emerge; 
whose not unequivocal joys Western Europe and Japan are beginning 
energetically to probe; and with which Soviet society is engaged in an 
uneasy flirtation. 
As societies achieved maturity in the twentieth century two things 
happened: real income per head rose to a point where a large number 
of persons gained a command over consumption which transcended 
basic food, shelter, and clothing; and the structure of the working 
force changed in ways which increased not only the proportion of 
urban to total population, but also the proportion of the population 
working in offices or in skilled factory jobs-aware of and anxious to 
acquire the consumption fruits of a mature economy. 
In addition to these economic changes, the society ceased to accept 
the further extension of modern technology as an overriding objective. 
It is in this post-maturity stage, for example, that, through the political 
process, Western societies have chosen to allocate increased resources 
to social welfare and security. The emergence of the welfare state is 
one manifestation of a society's moving beyond technical maturity; but 
it is also at this stage that resources tend increasingly to be directed to 
the production of consumers' durables and to the diffusion of services 
on a mass basis, if consumers' sovereignty reigns. The sewing-machine, 
the bicycle, and then the various electric-powered household 
gadgets were gradually diffused. Historically, however, the decisive 
element has been the cheap mass automobile with its quite 
revolutionary effects--social as well as economic--on the life and 
expectations of society. 
For the United States, the turning point was, perhaps, Henry Ford's 
moving assembly line of 1913-14; but it was in the 1920's, and again 
in the post-war decade, 1946-56, that this stage of growth was 
pressed to, virtually, its logical conclusion. In the 1950's Western 
Europe and Japan appear to have fully entered this phase, accounting 
substantially for a momentum in their economies quite unexpected in 
the immediate post-war years. The Soviet Union is technically ready 
for this stage, and, by every sign, its citizens hunger for it; but 
Communist leaders face difficult political and social problems of 
adjustment if this stage is launched. 
BEYOND CONSUMPTION 
Beyond, it is impossible to predict, except perhaps to observe that 
Americans, at least, have behaved in the past decade as if diminishing 
relative marginal utility sets in, after a point, for durable consumers' 
goods; and they have chosen, at the margin, larger families-behaviour 
in the pattern of Buddenbrooks dynamics.*
Civil society and economic development

Contenu connexe

Tendances

Co- creating Democracy: Roeland Japp in't Veld
Co- creating Democracy: Roeland Japp in't VeldCo- creating Democracy: Roeland Japp in't Veld
Co- creating Democracy: Roeland Japp in't Veld
Social Innovation Exchange
 
Ludger helms media and politics
Ludger helms media and politicsLudger helms media and politics
Ludger helms media and politics
Slugger Consults
 
Social Capital and Grassroots Development
Social Capital and Grassroots DevelopmentSocial Capital and Grassroots Development
Social Capital and Grassroots Development
Celeste Brubaker
 
An Analysis Of The Representation Of Democratic Citizenship In
An Analysis Of The Representation Of Democratic Citizenship InAn Analysis Of The Representation Of Democratic Citizenship In
An Analysis Of The Representation Of Democratic Citizenship In
legal2
 
Matilde-Giglio Dissertation
Matilde-Giglio DissertationMatilde-Giglio Dissertation
Matilde-Giglio Dissertation
Matilde Giglio
 
Week 5 - Reflective Response to Reading
Week 5 - Reflective Response to ReadingWeek 5 - Reflective Response to Reading
Week 5 - Reflective Response to Reading
Gemma
 

Tendances (19)

Theories of bureaucratic politics ppt
Theories of bureaucratic politics pptTheories of bureaucratic politics ppt
Theories of bureaucratic politics ppt
 
Co- creating Democracy: Roeland Japp in't Veld
Co- creating Democracy: Roeland Japp in't VeldCo- creating Democracy: Roeland Japp in't Veld
Co- creating Democracy: Roeland Japp in't Veld
 
The expressive turn of political participation in the digital age
The expressive turn of political participation in the digital ageThe expressive turn of political participation in the digital age
The expressive turn of political participation in the digital age
 
State and society in the process of democratization
State and society in the process of democratizationState and society in the process of democratization
State and society in the process of democratization
 
Ludger helms media and politics
Ludger helms media and politicsLudger helms media and politics
Ludger helms media and politics
 
SociologyExchange.co.uk Shared Resource
SociologyExchange.co.uk Shared ResourceSociologyExchange.co.uk Shared Resource
SociologyExchange.co.uk Shared Resource
 
The Broadening and Mystified Margins of Housing Deprivation
The Broadening and Mystified Margins of Housing DeprivationThe Broadening and Mystified Margins of Housing Deprivation
The Broadening and Mystified Margins of Housing Deprivation
 
Social Capital and Grassroots Development
Social Capital and Grassroots DevelopmentSocial Capital and Grassroots Development
Social Capital and Grassroots Development
 
What is democracy
What is democracyWhat is democracy
What is democracy
 
An Analysis Of The Representation Of Democratic Citizenship In
An Analysis Of The Representation Of Democratic Citizenship InAn Analysis Of The Representation Of Democratic Citizenship In
An Analysis Of The Representation Of Democratic Citizenship In
 
Human dignity, rights, and the common good what is citizenship and why does...
Human dignity, rights, and the common good   what is citizenship and why does...Human dignity, rights, and the common good   what is citizenship and why does...
Human dignity, rights, and the common good what is citizenship and why does...
 
Human dignity rights and the common good
Human dignity rights and the common goodHuman dignity rights and the common good
Human dignity rights and the common good
 
Matilde-Giglio Dissertation
Matilde-Giglio DissertationMatilde-Giglio Dissertation
Matilde-Giglio Dissertation
 
Week 1 politics and power history fair start representation and political pro...
Week 1 politics and power history fair start representation and political pro...Week 1 politics and power history fair start representation and political pro...
Week 1 politics and power history fair start representation and political pro...
 
Hacia un método inductivo para investigar la formación de valores con respect...
Hacia un método inductivo para investigar la formación de valores con respect...Hacia un método inductivo para investigar la formación de valores con respect...
Hacia un método inductivo para investigar la formación de valores con respect...
 
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #2
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #2Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #2
Political Science 2 – Comparative Politics - Power Point #2
 
Week 5 - Reflective Response to Reading
Week 5 - Reflective Response to ReadingWeek 5 - Reflective Response to Reading
Week 5 - Reflective Response to Reading
 
Political Activity of Women and Men – the Psychosocial Determinants of Conven...
Political Activity of Women and Men – the Psychosocial Determinants of Conven...Political Activity of Women and Men – the Psychosocial Determinants of Conven...
Political Activity of Women and Men – the Psychosocial Determinants of Conven...
 
Social capital, institutional trust and political accountability: The case fo...
Social capital, institutional trust and political accountability: The case fo...Social capital, institutional trust and political accountability: The case fo...
Social capital, institutional trust and political accountability: The case fo...
 

En vedette

Human Rights Presentation
Human Rights PresentationHuman Rights Presentation
Human Rights Presentation
ellaboi
 
Early and middle childhood cognitive development
Early and middle childhood cognitive developmentEarly and middle childhood cognitive development
Early and middle childhood cognitive development
ellaboi
 
Japanese period
Japanese periodJapanese period
Japanese period
ellaboi
 
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakataoBanghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao
ellaboi
 
Human Rights
Human RightsHuman Rights
Human Rights
Tian Xian
 

En vedette (11)

Human Rights Presentation
Human Rights PresentationHuman Rights Presentation
Human Rights Presentation
 
Early and middle childhood cognitive development
Early and middle childhood cognitive developmentEarly and middle childhood cognitive development
Early and middle childhood cognitive development
 
Human rights
Human rightsHuman rights
Human rights
 
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao 8 unang araw
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao 8 unang arawBanghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao 8 unang araw
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao 8 unang araw
 
Human rights (Universal Declaration of Human Rights)
Human rights (Universal Declaration of Human Rights)Human rights (Universal Declaration of Human Rights)
Human rights (Universal Declaration of Human Rights)
 
Japanese period
Japanese periodJapanese period
Japanese period
 
Human rights powerpoint
Human rights powerpointHuman rights powerpoint
Human rights powerpoint
 
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakataoBanghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao
Banghay aralin sa edukasyon sa pagpapakatao
 
Human rights
Human rightsHuman rights
Human rights
 
Human Rights
Human RightsHuman Rights
Human Rights
 
Detailed Lesson Plan (ENGLISH, MATH, SCIENCE, FILIPINO)
Detailed Lesson Plan (ENGLISH, MATH, SCIENCE, FILIPINO)Detailed Lesson Plan (ENGLISH, MATH, SCIENCE, FILIPINO)
Detailed Lesson Plan (ENGLISH, MATH, SCIENCE, FILIPINO)
 

Similaire à Civil society and economic development

07 04-2015 russia power point presentation
07 04-2015 russia power point presentation07 04-2015 russia power point presentation
07 04-2015 russia power point presentation
Anastasia Yakunina
 
Essays On Democracy. College of the Florida Keys
Essays On Democracy. College of the Florida KeysEssays On Democracy. College of the Florida Keys
Essays On Democracy. College of the Florida Keys
April Eide
 
Debate on Future Democracy and Corruption, in the Digital Age (from Theory to...
Debate on Future Democracy and Corruption, in the Digital Age (from Theory to...Debate on Future Democracy and Corruption, in the Digital Age (from Theory to...
Debate on Future Democracy and Corruption, in the Digital Age (from Theory to...
AJHSSR Journal
 
Copyright © 1995 The National Endowment for Democracy and The .docx
Copyright © 1995 The National Endowment for Democracy and The .docxCopyright © 1995 The National Endowment for Democracy and The .docx
Copyright © 1995 The National Endowment for Democracy and The .docx
vanesaburnand
 
Chapter 2 States and democracy, by prof RAAKICI
Chapter 2 States and democracy, by prof RAAKICIChapter 2 States and democracy, by prof RAAKICI
Chapter 2 States and democracy, by prof RAAKICI
Mukhtar-rakici Abdalla
 
Challenges of the Democracy of the Future, in the Digital Society (from Theor...
Challenges of the Democracy of the Future, in the Digital Society (from Theor...Challenges of the Democracy of the Future, in the Digital Society (from Theor...
Challenges of the Democracy of the Future, in the Digital Society (from Theor...
AJHSSR Journal
 
Transforming Governance
Transforming GovernanceTransforming Governance
Transforming Governance
Nicole Cabral
 

Similaire à Civil society and economic development (20)

Aartscholteaccountable
AartscholteaccountableAartscholteaccountable
Aartscholteaccountable
 
assessing-the-quality-of-democracy-a-practical-guide.pdf
assessing-the-quality-of-democracy-a-practical-guide.pdfassessing-the-quality-of-democracy-a-practical-guide.pdf
assessing-the-quality-of-democracy-a-practical-guide.pdf
 
Analytical Approaches To The Study Of Politics In The Developing World
Analytical Approaches To The Study Of Politics In The Developing WorldAnalytical Approaches To The Study Of Politics In The Developing World
Analytical Approaches To The Study Of Politics In The Developing World
 
GOVT ESSAY
GOVT ESSAYGOVT ESSAY
GOVT ESSAY
 
07 04-2015 russia power point presentation
07 04-2015 russia power point presentation07 04-2015 russia power point presentation
07 04-2015 russia power point presentation
 
Essays On Democracy. College of the Florida Keys
Essays On Democracy. College of the Florida KeysEssays On Democracy. College of the Florida Keys
Essays On Democracy. College of the Florida Keys
 
Democracy Essays.pdf
Democracy Essays.pdfDemocracy Essays.pdf
Democracy Essays.pdf
 
Debate on Future Democracy and Corruption, in the Digital Age (from Theory to...
Debate on Future Democracy and Corruption, in the Digital Age (from Theory to...Debate on Future Democracy and Corruption, in the Digital Age (from Theory to...
Debate on Future Democracy and Corruption, in the Digital Age (from Theory to...
 
Essay On Importance Of Democracy.pdf
Essay On Importance Of Democracy.pdfEssay On Importance Of Democracy.pdf
Essay On Importance Of Democracy.pdf
 
Democratization, media and elections: Electoral reform in Mexico
Democratization, media and elections:  Electoral reform in MexicoDemocratization, media and elections:  Electoral reform in Mexico
Democratization, media and elections: Electoral reform in Mexico
 
Extreme Democracy; Networks
Extreme Democracy; NetworksExtreme Democracy; Networks
Extreme Democracy; Networks
 
Essay Democracy.pdf
Essay Democracy.pdfEssay Democracy.pdf
Essay Democracy.pdf
 
Copyright © 1995 The National Endowment for Democracy and The .docx
Copyright © 1995 The National Endowment for Democracy and The .docxCopyright © 1995 The National Endowment for Democracy and The .docx
Copyright © 1995 The National Endowment for Democracy and The .docx
 
Chapter 2 States and democracy, by prof RAAKICI
Chapter 2 States and democracy, by prof RAAKICIChapter 2 States and democracy, by prof RAAKICI
Chapter 2 States and democracy, by prof RAAKICI
 
Write An Essay On Democracy.pdf
Write An Essay On Democracy.pdfWrite An Essay On Democracy.pdf
Write An Essay On Democracy.pdf
 
The Third Era (highlight booklet)
The Third Era (highlight booklet)The Third Era (highlight booklet)
The Third Era (highlight booklet)
 
The dilemmas of the developmental state: democracy and economic development i...
The dilemmas of the developmental state: democracy and economic development i...The dilemmas of the developmental state: democracy and economic development i...
The dilemmas of the developmental state: democracy and economic development i...
 
Challenges of the Democracy of the Future, in the Digital Society (from Theor...
Challenges of the Democracy of the Future, in the Digital Society (from Theor...Challenges of the Democracy of the Future, in the Digital Society (from Theor...
Challenges of the Democracy of the Future, in the Digital Society (from Theor...
 
Transforming Governance
Transforming GovernanceTransforming Governance
Transforming Governance
 
co.pol
co.polco.pol
co.pol
 

Plus de ellaboi

Literature during medieval period
Literature during medieval periodLiterature during medieval period
Literature during medieval period
ellaboi
 
Sociological theories and the education system
Sociological theories and the education systemSociological theories and the education system
Sociological theories and the education system
ellaboi
 
Foundational principles of morality
Foundational principles of moralityFoundational principles of morality
Foundational principles of morality
ellaboi
 
Types of behavioral disorders
Types of behavioral disordersTypes of behavioral disorders
Types of behavioral disorders
ellaboi
 
Montessori approach to behavioral disorders
Montessori approach to behavioral disordersMontessori approach to behavioral disorders
Montessori approach to behavioral disorders
ellaboi
 
Educational system in united kingdom
Educational system in united kingdomEducational system in united kingdom
Educational system in united kingdom
ellaboi
 
MR Early Intervention Approcahes
MR Early Intervention ApprocahesMR Early Intervention Approcahes
MR Early Intervention Approcahes
ellaboi
 
Lpwh exploration
Lpwh explorationLpwh exploration
Lpwh exploration
ellaboi
 
Lpkas himagsikan 2
Lpkas himagsikan 2Lpkas himagsikan 2
Lpkas himagsikan 2
ellaboi
 
Lpkas himagsikan 1
Lpkas himagsikan 1Lpkas himagsikan 1
Lpkas himagsikan 1
ellaboi
 
100 yearswar
100 yearswar100 yearswar
100 yearswar
ellaboi
 
Plague and hundred years war
Plague and hundred years warPlague and hundred years war
Plague and hundred years war
ellaboi
 
Lpwh hundred years war
Lpwh hundred years warLpwh hundred years war
Lpwh hundred years war
ellaboi
 
Self awareness and Self Management
Self awareness and Self ManagementSelf awareness and Self Management
Self awareness and Self Management
ellaboi
 
Chapter 8 cold war (edsel jasmine sison's conflicted copy 2013 03-07)
Chapter 8 cold war (edsel jasmine sison's conflicted copy 2013 03-07)Chapter 8 cold war (edsel jasmine sison's conflicted copy 2013 03-07)
Chapter 8 cold war (edsel jasmine sison's conflicted copy 2013 03-07)
ellaboi
 

Plus de ellaboi (17)

Literature during medieval period
Literature during medieval periodLiterature during medieval period
Literature during medieval period
 
Sociological theories and the education system
Sociological theories and the education systemSociological theories and the education system
Sociological theories and the education system
 
Foundational principles of morality
Foundational principles of moralityFoundational principles of morality
Foundational principles of morality
 
Types of behavioral disorders
Types of behavioral disordersTypes of behavioral disorders
Types of behavioral disorders
 
Montessori approach to behavioral disorders
Montessori approach to behavioral disordersMontessori approach to behavioral disorders
Montessori approach to behavioral disorders
 
Educational system in united kingdom
Educational system in united kingdomEducational system in united kingdom
Educational system in united kingdom
 
MR Early Intervention Approcahes
MR Early Intervention ApprocahesMR Early Intervention Approcahes
MR Early Intervention Approcahes
 
Lpwh exploration
Lpwh explorationLpwh exploration
Lpwh exploration
 
Lpkas himagsikan 2
Lpkas himagsikan 2Lpkas himagsikan 2
Lpkas himagsikan 2
 
Lpkas himagsikan 1
Lpkas himagsikan 1Lpkas himagsikan 1
Lpkas himagsikan 1
 
100 yearswar
100 yearswar100 yearswar
100 yearswar
 
Plague and hundred years war
Plague and hundred years warPlague and hundred years war
Plague and hundred years war
 
Lpwh hundred years war
Lpwh hundred years warLpwh hundred years war
Lpwh hundred years war
 
Quiz 1 kasaysayan ng daigdig
Quiz 1 kasaysayan ng daigdigQuiz 1 kasaysayan ng daigdig
Quiz 1 kasaysayan ng daigdig
 
Self awareness and Self Management
Self awareness and Self ManagementSelf awareness and Self Management
Self awareness and Self Management
 
Debate motions
Debate motionsDebate motions
Debate motions
 
Chapter 8 cold war (edsel jasmine sison's conflicted copy 2013 03-07)
Chapter 8 cold war (edsel jasmine sison's conflicted copy 2013 03-07)Chapter 8 cold war (edsel jasmine sison's conflicted copy 2013 03-07)
Chapter 8 cold war (edsel jasmine sison's conflicted copy 2013 03-07)
 

Dernier

Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptxSeal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
negromaestrong
 
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
QucHHunhnh
 
Gardella_PRCampaignConclusion Pitch Letter
Gardella_PRCampaignConclusion Pitch LetterGardella_PRCampaignConclusion Pitch Letter
Gardella_PRCampaignConclusion Pitch Letter
MateoGardella
 
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfActivity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
ciinovamais
 

Dernier (20)

Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptxSeal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
Seal of Good Local Governance (SGLG) 2024Final.pptx
 
Measures of Dispersion and Variability: Range, QD, AD and SD
Measures of Dispersion and Variability: Range, QD, AD and SDMeasures of Dispersion and Variability: Range, QD, AD and SD
Measures of Dispersion and Variability: Range, QD, AD and SD
 
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
Sports & Fitness Value Added Course FY..
 
Unit-IV; Professional Sales Representative (PSR).pptx
Unit-IV; Professional Sales Representative (PSR).pptxUnit-IV; Professional Sales Representative (PSR).pptx
Unit-IV; Professional Sales Representative (PSR).pptx
 
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi  6.pdf
1029-Danh muc Sach Giao Khoa khoi 6.pdf
 
ICT Role in 21st Century Education & its Challenges.pptx
ICT Role in 21st Century Education & its Challenges.pptxICT Role in 21st Century Education & its Challenges.pptx
ICT Role in 21st Century Education & its Challenges.pptx
 
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17 How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17  How to Extend Models Using Mixin ClassesMixin Classes in Odoo 17  How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
Mixin Classes in Odoo 17 How to Extend Models Using Mixin Classes
 
Gardella_PRCampaignConclusion Pitch Letter
Gardella_PRCampaignConclusion Pitch LetterGardella_PRCampaignConclusion Pitch Letter
Gardella_PRCampaignConclusion Pitch Letter
 
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
Mattingly "AI & Prompt Design: The Basics of Prompt Design"
 
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptxUnit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
Unit-IV- Pharma. Marketing Channels.pptx
 
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
Explore beautiful and ugly buildings. Mathematics helps us create beautiful d...
 
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdfActivity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
Activity 01 - Artificial Culture (1).pdf
 
PROCESS RECORDING FORMAT.docx
PROCESS      RECORDING        FORMAT.docxPROCESS      RECORDING        FORMAT.docx
PROCESS RECORDING FORMAT.docx
 
psychiatric nursing HISTORY COLLECTION .docx
psychiatric  nursing HISTORY  COLLECTION  .docxpsychiatric  nursing HISTORY  COLLECTION  .docx
psychiatric nursing HISTORY COLLECTION .docx
 
Advance Mobile Application Development class 07
Advance Mobile Application Development class 07Advance Mobile Application Development class 07
Advance Mobile Application Development class 07
 
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across SectorsAPM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
APM Welcome, APM North West Network Conference, Synergies Across Sectors
 
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdfKey note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
Key note speaker Neum_Admir Softic_ENG.pdf
 
Application orientated numerical on hev.ppt
Application orientated numerical on hev.pptApplication orientated numerical on hev.ppt
Application orientated numerical on hev.ppt
 
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and ModeMeasures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
Measures of Central Tendency: Mean, Median and Mode
 
Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptxUnit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
Unit-V; Pricing (Pharma Marketing Management).pptx
 

Civil society and economic development

  • 1. Civil Society and the Problem of Global Democracy MICHAEL GOODHART Civil society is among the most widely discussed and frequently deployed concepts in contemporary political science. To normative political theorists it is a critical concept representing an ideal of inclusive participation and deliberation. Many empirically minded students of democracy emphasize its role in fostering democratic transitions and facilitating democratic consolidation. Moreover, political scientists of many stripes have taken an interest in the various actors who populate civil society – from non-governmental organizations (NGOs) and new social movements to the more traditional interest groups emphasized in the pluralist framework. Of late there has been a veritable explosion of new work on civil society in its many guises, and while some skeptical voices have questioned the sanguine views currently in vogue, the judgment expressed in the Times Literary Supplement remains apt: ‘the very phrase [civil society] is becoming motherhood-and-apple- pie’.1 Ironically, as enthusiasm about civil society’s role in supporting democracy grows, the prospects of democracy itself seem to be worsening. Over the past decade, the accelerating pace of globalization has fueled alarm over the vitality of state-level democracy and over the lack of democracy in international, transnational and global institutions and interactions. Democratic deficits and disjunctures, created by the seemingly relentless advance of globalization and by the state’s alleged ‘retreat’ or ‘erosion’ before it, have forced scholars to reconsider democracy’s foundations at the nation-state level and to contemplate schemes for implementing it globally. ‘The problem of global democracy’ is a shorthand for such concerns about globalization’s perceived adverse effects; quite basically, the problem is whether and how democracy can weather these challenges. Perhaps inevitably, given the concurrence of these two significant developments, many scholars and activists have begun to conceive of an emergent ‘global civil society’ as a model or strategy for global democracy and democratization. These theorists and practitioners increasingly adopt global civil society (GCS) as a conceptual framework for supranational democracy and as a concrete political project. They propose that, like its domestic counterpart, GCS has great potential as a site and mechanism of global democracy and as a vehicle for democratizing supranational governance. This article critically evaluates these claims, advancing two closely related arguments. The first, substantive argument is that proponents of global democracy through GCS do not adequately conceptualize global democracy or democratization: civil society’s purported democratic functions and effects do not and cannot work in the supranational setting. The second, epistemological argument is that the failure of GCS as an account of global democracy and democratization reflects broader challenges in theorizing global politics and global democracy. Democratic enthusiasm for GCS confuses the challenges facing democracy and mistakenly relies on concepts and theories of democracy rooted in Westphalian politics in addressing them. As the problems with GCS accounts illustrate, meeting these challenges requires a global democratic theory, not simply the global application or extension of existing democratic theory. The article has four sections. The first introduces the problem of global democracy and briefly reviews the main claims for conceiving GCS as a model or strategy for global democracy in response to this problem. These claims draw on two models of civil society’s democratic functions and effects in the state, the neo-Tocquevillian and anti-authoritarian models. Sections two and three analyse each model in turn, showing that neither successfully survives transposition to the supranational sphere. Civil society cannot perform its democratic role because that role depends on conceptual and institutional relationships that do not hold globally. The final section shows that the shortcomings of GCS as a model for global democracy reflect common epistemological errors in the analysis of supranational politics and the theorization of global democracy. These errors include conceiving global politics in statist ways and treating the problem of global democracy mainly as a problem of size or reach. A theory of global democracy must reconsider the meaning and institutional form of democracy in light of the distinctive characteristics of globalization and supranational governance. Before beginning, however, two potential points of confusion should be pre-empted. First, the argument here does not question the political significance of supranational network and associational activity. A vast empirical literature documents how GCS can influence policy and constrain global governance. Moreover, many GCS actors are motivated by and promote norms of democracy and human rights. These facts are acknowledged and appreciated, and nothing here should be taken to prejudge what role supranational network and associational actors might 2 DEMOCRATIZATION play in achieving and sustaining global democracy. Second, and following closely from the preceding point, the argument here is not about whether GCS is a good thing or has positive effects on global governance. Undoubtedly it can do so, and numerous scholars have paid careful attention to how.2 The argument rather concerns whether GCS provides an adequate and appropriate model for global democracy and strategy for global democratization – that is, whether we should conceive global democracy in terms of GCS. The negative conclusion is based on a conceptual critique of global democracy on the GCS model, not on a denial or rejection of the positive potential contributions of supranational network and associational activity. GCS: A Model for Global Democracy? Before considering arguments proposing GCS as a model for global democracy, a few words about the problem of global democracy are in order. Globalization is widely perceived as a threat to democracy within states and as intensifying the need for greater democracy among states. While a full discussion of these issues is beyond the scope of this article the crucial points can be sketched briefly.3 Globalization is a contested concept, one encompassing change in technological, military, cultural, political, and perhaps especially economic domains. The essence of this change can be characterized as supranationalization, a shift in the locus or density of social activity and interactions (including governance) from the local and national to the supranational (international, transnational and global) level. This quite general understanding of globalization makes its challenges for democracy seemingly clear. First, globalization creates democratic disjunctures, which describe the gap between existing state-level democratic procedures and institutions and the increasingly supranational character of many political issues, including terrorism, public health, the environment and, most controversially, trade, investment and economic integration. Second, globalization exposes and exacerbates democratic deficits, which describe the lack of transparency, accountability and representation in existing supranational institutions.4 The problem of global democracy is how meaningfully to realize democracy outside its traditional theoretical and institutional boundaries in the Westphalian state without further attenuating democracy within them. Many scholars attribute the rapid development of GCS to a shift of power away from states to both supranational and subnational authorities. This shift, they contend, creates a need for new actors to assume many of the functions previously performed by states, including identity formation and preservation, regulation of the economy, protection of the environment and articulation of the needs and interests of citizens. The actors populating GCS fill a void created by the retreat of the state and the spread of global capitalism,5 in effect bridging democratic disjunctures and compensating for democratic deficits. Growing numbers of democratic theorists and activists, observing the proliferation of supranational NGOs and transnational social movements (TSMs) and impressed by their increasing role and influence in supranational affairs, talk about GCS as a model or framework for global democracy.6 To its proponents, the role of GCS as a democratic model originates in and is ‘legitimated by the growing competence of societal actors relative to the inability CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 3 of states to confront problems that increasingly escape the grasp of territorially delimited actors’.7 On this view, the nascent sphere of GCS overlays the existing political spaces of states and international politics, allowing ‘for the construction of new political spaces . . . delineated by networks of economic, social and cultural relations . . . occupied by the conscious association of actors, in physically separated locations, who link themselves together in networks for particular political and social purposes’.8 A ‘medley of boundary-eclipsing actors – social movements, interest groups, indigenous peoples, cultural groups, and global citizens – are [sic] seen to be constructing networks, knowledges and practices that entail a reshaping of the political architecture of international relations’.9 These networks and associations counterbalance the ‘state-like’ system of global governance made up of institutionalized regulatory arrangements (regimes) and less formalized norms, rules and procedures.10 Proponents see numerous democratic functions and effects in the activities of these new transnational actors. The constituent groups of GCS are voluntary and often issue or identity related; they seek social or political influence and generate bonds and social capital across state borders. These groups serve as channels for information, creating opportunities for transnational learning and dialogue that facilitate the recognition of common experiences of global problems and the emergence of transnational identities.11 According to Smith, global groups and networks also represent ‘the most promising source of enhanced democratic participation in the emerging global polity’.12 In her view, participation in TSM organizations ‘helps enfranchise individuals and groups that are formally excluded from participation in international institutions. It strengthens the global public sphere by mobilizing this disenfranchised public into discussions of global issues, thereby democratizing the global political process’. Participation thus serves a representative function that widens discussion of the global public good and expands both the agenda and the range of policy options considered. Transnational networks, ranging in intensity from informal contacts based around shared values to full-fledged TSMs, characterize activism targeting particular global issues and institutions.13 Their influence derives from their efficacy in shaping the international agenda, in negotiating within various international forums, in strengthening and supporting local organizations and networks, and in using their moral authority to pressure officials and raise consciousness.14 Such networks frequently draw on already-established norms of democracy and human rights to construct frames for collective action and opposition to oppressive regimes.15 GCS can claim some success in influencing states and international regimes; the expanding role of NGOs and TSM organizations in global summits and conferences and even in some formal governance regimes further encourages the hope that they might play an important role in democratization.16 Dryzek, for example, concludes that GCS can provide democratic legitimacy to the emerging system of global governance. Deepening transnational discourses facilitated by NGOs and TSMs have become dense enough in his view to constitute discursive networks capable of shaping global opinion.17 Networks promoting transnational deliberation (and thus shaping transnational discourse) are ‘the most appropriate available institutional expression 4 DEMOCRATIZATION of a dispersed capacity to engage in deliberation’ that promotes democratic legitimacy. 18 Seen in this broader context, one aim of GCS is to reconnect politics with the moral purpose and values associated with democracy. Falk and others refer to this process as one of ‘globalization from below’, in which grass- and cyber-roots activities (will) remake the international order through civilizing activities based in a commitment to progressive political norms.19 Two related but distinct kinds of claim about the democratic nature of GCS are discernible in the arguments just surveyed. One is that institutional activity within GCS – including the transfer of information, creation of social bonds, representation of diverse interests and deliberation on important issues – is democratic and thus helps make global governance (more) democratic. The other is that networks and movements committed to democratic and human rights norms will transform the international regime through opposition to and renewal of existing non-democratic governance structures. These two types of claim evoke two different models or ideal types of civil society in the state, what are called here the neo- Tocquevillian and anti-authoritarian models.20 Because GCS is complex and embryonic, these models have become blurred and confused in claims about the democratic nature of GCS. In order to gain analytic leverage in evaluating them, the following account specifies the purported democratic functions and effects of each model at the domestic level and then considers whether they obtain in the global context. The analysis focuses on the often-implicit assumptions underlying these democratic claims and on their empirical, pragmatic and normative implications.21 The Neo-Tocquevillian Model The neo-Tocquevillian model emphasizes the democratic functions and effects of associational life within a liberal or liberal-democratic state. It theorizes this associational sphere as autonomous, occupying a conceptual space between the individual
  • 2. and the state. Civil society ‘[names] the space of uncoerced human association and also the set of relational networks . . . that fill this space’,22 although there is disagreement about whether to include the family and market actors and institutions in this definition.23 Liberals, communitarians (republicans) and critical theorists have all embraced some variant of this model.24 The essence of the neo-Tocquevillian approach is ‘that largely apolitical associations that crosscut the major lines of conflict within a society will help produce the moderation and the compromising spirit necessary for efficient democratic governance’.25 These institutions ‘counterbalance the state and, while not preventing the state from fulfilling its role of keeper of the peace and arbitrator between major interests, can nevertheless prevent it from dominating and atomizing the rest of society’.26 Activity and participation within the autonomous sphere recognize and promote the values of publicity, participation and state accountability by mobilizing independent political actors and protecting subjective rights in a context governed by the rule of law.27 Some theorists correlate the sheer density of associations with the vitality of democracy, while others focus on the habits and values inculcated by citizens’ immersion in associational life. Involvement with voluntary associations CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 5 teaches individuals to put common values ahead of selfish interests, creates social capital and helps to undercut the tremendous power of the modern bureaucratic state.28 Many theorists of discursive or deliberative democracy see civil society’s independent networks and associations as an approximation of an ideal discursive arena where open, unconstrained deliberation generates norms that produce consensus and guide democratic practice.29 As this discussion makes clear, the neo-Tocquevillian model is not merely a descriptive account of civil society and its operations; nor is it a complete account of democracy. Rather, it tries to explain how a well-functioning civil society supports and facilitates democracy. Five distinct claims can be distilled from the foregoing account. First, participation in voluntary associations educates people to be good democratic citizens; they learn to co-operate, to put public ends ahead of private ones, and so forth. Second, participation creates a moderate public and moderates public opinion. Third, participation helps to build social capital among individuals, giving cohesion to communities and amplifying citizens’ capabilities. Fourth, networks in civil society crosscut power relations and hierarchies in the state, thwarting the dominance of any group or interest and providing an alternate means of representation. Finally, civil society provides a site for the discursive will formation that generates democratic legitimacy. Each of these claims rests on empirical foundations that might well be challenged. Most accounts of civil society, for instance, ignore such networks and associations as skinheads, neo-fascists and criminal gangs, raising serious questions about many of the claims just surveyed.30 Rosenblum warns that civil society is varied and complex, its moral and political effects difficult to discern and perhaps ultimately indeterminate thanks precisely to the immense variety and complexity of associational forms and activity. While this pluralism should be valued for its contribution to freedom, it should not be naively conflated with a logic of congruence that assumes the uniformity of associational life or the generalizability of its effects.31 So far, moreover, hypotheses about civil society’s democratic effects have not been adequately tested, though Warren has clarified the myriad of claims and specified features of associations that might help us gauge their democratic effects.32 Nonetheless, these empirical hypotheses are accepted provisionally so as to concentrate instead on some frequently overlooked assumptions about the relationship between the state and civil society on which the latter’s purported democratic functions and effects depend conceptually.33 The first assumption is that civil society and the state are coterminous. Civil society takes the state’s territory, jurisdiction and membership as its parameters. While the autonomous sphere of associational life occupies a distinct conceptual space, that space is delimited practically by the borders of the state. The members of civil society are simply the citizens of the state; the entire population is not necessarily included, or included equally, but when we talk about civil society in the United States, say, we accept implicitly that it does not include Mexican social movements or Canadian bowling leagues. Similarly, to the extent that we can talk about Canadian civil society, we acknowledge that it is coterminous with the Canadian state and its territory. Finally, civil society requires political authorities and institutions with jurisdiction within its territory 6 DEMOCRATIZATION and over its members; it presumes some fit between the location of its activities and the location of state control or authority. In short, civil society on this model assumes a territorial state. This is hardly surprising; most modern political theory takes the state for granted.34 Still, this statist assumption is crucial in making sense of civil society’s democratic functions. Its significance is demonstrated through a second assumption – that there is ‘democratic symmetry’ between civil society and the state. The state is the appropriate container of politics and vehicle for democracy; rightful rule attaches to a particular territory. As Held puts it, there is a ‘“natural community of fate” – a community which rightly governs itself and determines its own future’.35 This symmetry is crucial to civil society’s role as a site for discursive will formation that guides or determines state policy and provides democratic legitimacy. Given that civil society is independent of the political sphere by definition, this function can only be democratic if there is an identity between civil society’s members and the state’s citizenry and if their will translates into law or policy only within the political community they share. To take a simplistic example, the implementation in Canadian law or policy of public opinion distilled through the serious, public-spirited deliberation of independent Mexican civic associations would not count as democratic. What matters is not merely the formation of public opinion according to norms of publicity and openness but also which public does the formulating. Conceiving civil society as a political community of fate reconciles the formation of public opinion and the generation of political demands with the necessary use of state power to enact or enable policies. The issue is less capacity than authority, the recognized and legitimate exercise of state power in a particular territory. This ‘democratic symmetry’ simply but importantly reflects the foundation of the liberal-democratic state in the doctrine of popular sovereignty.36 A third central assumption underpinning neo-Tocquevillian civil society’s democratic effects is that civil society and the state are mutually supportive and constitutive. 37 The state’s laws structure civil society, defining its members’ rights and its civic spaces. The state’s institutions uphold the laws, regulating activities within civil society and guaranteeing rights;38 they are responsive to the demands of civil society, providing points of access and influence. The state’s norms shape civil society and the groups populating it; as Walzer puts it, ‘only a democratic state can create a democratic civil society, and only a democratic civil society can sustain a democratic state’.39 There is an obvious but instructive circularity here: the purported democratic functions and effects of civil society can only work in the context of a democratic state where participation, representation and deliberation are valued and institutionalized politically; only in these circumstances does civil society strengthen and support political democracy. This virtuous circle is the heart of the democratic case for civil society on the neo-Tocquevillian model. Identifying the interdependence of state and civil society in the neo- Tocquevillian model in no way constitutes a criticism; it simply makes explicit the assumptions upon which the model’s democratic claims depend. I acknowledge that both in principle and in practice associational life might manifest many of its salutary effects quite apart from the state – in large associations, in non-governmental institutions CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 7 and in local communities of various kinds. Still, to reiterate, we cannot understand these effects to be ancillary to political democracy in the state – as champions of the neo-Tocquevillian model undoubtedly do – without understanding the interdependence of state and civil society on which they depend conceptually. Many (perhaps most) observers conceptualize GCS in neo-Tocquevillian fashion, emphasizing participation and trust-building through transnational networks, deliberation within global publics shaping norms and policy, representation of diverse global interests, demanding accountability from and providing a counterweight to global regimes, and so on.40 Certainly the constellation of transnational actors emphasized by proponents of GCS does in many respects resemble that in the neo- Tocquevillian model. Again, one might challenge the empirical hypotheses underlying these claims about the democratic effects of GCS.41 Instead, however, the intention here is to look at whether the assumptions underlying the purported democratic effects of civil society obtain at the supranational level. The aim is not to make an empirical assessment of GCS activity but rather to critique its democratic potential conceptually. Take the first assumption – that civil society and the state are coterminous. Clearly this assumption breaks down at the global level. There is no global polity, no political unit whose borders, institutions and membership correspond with those of a potential GCS. At least three important difficulties follow. The first concerns membership of GCS: is everyone an equal member whose voice and interests should always count equally on every issue and in every decision? Or, since global governance regimes have different jurisdictions and constituencies, are some boundaries implied? Is there one global public or many regional ones? How are these determinations made? Another difficulty has to do with the high degree of institutional differentiation among international governance organizations (IGOs). It is true that IGOs perform ‘state-like’ functions – regulation, enforcement, coordination and so on. But they are typically organized functionally rather than territorially, creating a patchwork of overlapping and fragmented jurisdictions that some writers liken to a ‘new medievalism’.42 The Westphalian state (at least mythically) established a unified authority and jurisdiction across all public functional domains. Progressive social change has historically depended upon this unity, upon a state possessing the authority to implement change throughout a society and its institutions; as Pasha and Blaney note, civil society itself often calls forth an expansion of the state apparatus as an agent of social reform.43 One of the key achievements of the post-war democratic welfare state was subordinating the capitalist economy to public – democratic – authority. Where key governance institutions are not unified or even coordinated, democratic purposes become difficult to achieve and maintain. Finally, despite talk of ‘new’ political spaces, the supranational associational sphere overlays political spaces in particular states; thus GCS is highly differentiated politically, with significant implications for its democratic character. When the WTO holds a ministerial meeting in Seattle, civil society is relatively free to organize and stage protests because Seattle is located in a democratic state with a functioning democratic civil society. Things look much different when the meeting moves to Doha – and this was of course the point in moving it there. The difference is 8 DEMOCRATIZATION a function of accessibility, to be sure, but it is also immediately political: GCS is only as open or democratic as the political space (the state and civil society) in which it is manifest. Even users of the Internet – another new political space – must log on from somewhere, and the authorities there are showing an ever keener interest in what those users see and do. The second assumption, that the state and civil society share a democratic symmetry, also clearly does not hold at the supranational level. Democratic functions like representation of interests, participation, opinion formation and the balancing of competing interests all assume an institutionalized electoral connection that is clearly absent in GCS. The overlap between citizenship and membership in civil society at the state level means that each opinion is attached to a vote and thus carries weight with decision-makers. Since IGOs are unelected, this symmetry does not hold. Decision makers are not electorally accountable to constituents of GCS (except indirectly where democratically elected officials appoint them).44 Moreover, the asymmetry between IGOs and political communities of fate delegitimizes the democratic character of deliberation. Domestically, the state defines and delimits a demos, a self-governing political community; even if a global discourse could be truly open, inclusive, accessible and egalitarian – criteria which are utopian even in democratic states – it would lack democratic legitimacy precisely because it would not emanate from a political community previously acknowledged as legitimate by its members. Despite some heroic attempts to get around this problem, most notably by Held, there is no democratic way to define the demos; borders cannot in principle be drawn democratically because democracy presupposes the demos that takes decisions.45 Some theorists have imagined that GCS might ‘bootstrap’ out of this difficulty, discursively constituting the democratic community its legitimacy takes for granted, but this circle cannot circumscribe the problems of plausibility it creates.46 Moreover,
  • 3. without global political institutions to translate the public will into law and policy, it is not clear what the political meaning of global deliberations is or should be. Nor is it clear what would happen if the ‘global democratic will’ conflicted with the particular will of a democratic state.47 Given these difficulties, it becomes unclear what exactly the democratic functions of global opinion, discourse and deliberation might be.48 Finally, the neo-Tocquevillian model presumes that civil society and the state are mutually constitutive. We have seen that a democratic civil society requires the rule of law as well as explicit guarantees of citizens’ rights; it requires norms of openness, freedom, equality and participation; and it requires institutions that are open to influence and scrutiny by the public. This is what Walzer meant by saying that ‘only a democratic state can create a democratic civil society’ (emphasis mine). In considering GCS as a model of global democracy, however, we must also consider whether only a democratic state can create a democratic civil society. Global governance is not characterized by the rule of law; at the global level there is no extensive legal system and few institutions to enforce those important laws that do exist. The rights possessed by members of GCS are their rights as citizens of particular states, and they vary tremendously. While governance regimes perform many state-like functions, they typically do not guarantee anyone’s rights (which is not to say they CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 9 do not affect anyone’s rights). Moreover, while IGOs are responsible for much global governance, the absence of a global government means that a variety of other actors – from NGOs and TSMs to transnational corporations, organized crime, terrorist networks, private militias and sex traffickers – also exercises significant governance functions in the supranational domain. Many do not promote democracy locally, where they operate, or globally. States can – at least where they have the capacity – constrain the governance roles of such actors domestically, but their ability to do so supranationally is highly limited. Thus despite the exuberance of GCS advocates, non-state voluntary activity at the supranational level might on balance be detrimental to democratic norms; without a democratic state to support these norms and suppress non-democratic ones, a democratic GCSmight be impossible. In sum, GCS cannot support democracy in the way that neo-Tocquevillian civil society does because the latter’s democratic functions cannot work outside a democratic state. Empirically, GCS and domestic civil society are disanalogous in important ways; they describe different phenomena, and we have seen that those differences are directly relevant to the democratic role of civil society. Pragmatically, civil society strategies that help to reinforce democracy within the state – participation, deliberation and the like – lack the conceptual and institutional grounding on which their democratic functions and effects depend. Normatively, these differences raise important questions about the global applicability and relevance of the democratic ideal animating neo- Tocquevillian civil society. More on these problems below. The Anti-Authoritarian Model The anti-authoritarian model of civil society is best exemplified in the resistance and opposition politics of Latin America and Eastern Europe in the 1970s and 1980s.49 This model of civil society has been described as ‘antipolitics’, principled opposition to authoritarian regimes through individual and collective devotion to principles of civility, toleration, openness, human rights – in a word, democracy. Here civil society is not only separate from but also opposed to the state; it describes an ethical and political consciousness as well as the community of groups and individuals united in this consciousness.50 The essence of the anti-authoritarian model, as the name suggests, is opposition to the ubiquitous and intrusive institutions of oppressive rule; it was an attempt to renew politics by freeing citizens from the ‘suffocating burden’ these institutions imposed.51 On this understanding, ‘civil society was the name of the anti-authoritarian, anti-conformist impetus, rooted in the rediscovery of human rights and the possibility of non- Machiavellian politics’.52 It referred to the ‘autonomous space in society outside the purview of the totalitarian state and operating within the framework of democratic principles’.53 According to Gyo¨rgy Konrad, ‘antipolitics is the ethos of civil society, and civil society is the antithesis of military society’.54 This ‘ethos’ has also been described as ‘a normative sense [denoting] a set of values having to do with democracy and freedom’.55 As Va´clav Havel famously outlined in his essay ‘The Power of the Powerless’, dissent was the necessary first step in creating this ethos of resistance; it was 10 DEMOCRATIZATION unavoidably a step to be taken by individuals deciding to ‘live within the truth’56 – roughly, to reject ideology and embrace intellectual honesty, personal integrity and a democratic ethic. Adam Michnik, one of the founders of Solidarity, similarly argued that if people began living as if they inhabited a free society their actions would in themselves inaugurate the creation of a free public space.57 Such individual choices were nevertheless recognized as explicitly political, part of what Tismaneanu calls ‘the reinvention of politics outside the existing matrix of power’.58 Their political consequences would be ‘reflected in the constitution of structures that will derive from this new spirit, from human factors rather than from a particular formulation of political relationships and guarantees . . . The issue is the rehabilitation of values like trust, openness, responsibility, solidarity, love.’59 Thus the goal was two-fold: the rehabilitation of ‘civil’ or ‘civic’ values,60 and the eventual creation of what another prominent Czech dissident, Va´ clav Benda, called ‘the parallel polis’ – a symbolic set of social, economic and political structures wholly separate from the state that might one day take over the state. The anti-political stance that followed from this democratic ethos animated the activities of groups like Solidarity and the Workers Defense Committee (KOR) in Poland and Charter 77 in Czechoslovakia. As Havel put it, ‘the point where living within the truth ceases to be a mere negation of living within a lie and becomes articulate in a particular way is the point at which something is born that might be called the “independent spiritual, social, and political life of society” ’.61 Still, as Goldfarb notes, ‘opposition to dictatorship does not necessarily lead to democracy’.62 Indeed, as Michnik and others saw, anti-politics can only offer evolutionism as a theory of democratization.63 This transformative effort always had a crucial transnational dimension.64 The peace movements that operated on both sides of the Iron Curtain and the struggles for human rights in Eastern Europe and Latin America all relied on support, publicity and political pressure generated by transnational networks. This relationship is captured in the ‘spiral model’ developed by Risse and Sikkink, which explains how relatively weak social movements for human rights and democracy in authoritarian countries managed to have such profound transformative effects on entrenched and intransigent regimes.65 Dissident and opposition groups proved amazingly successful in highlighting governments’ failures to abide by their public commitments to democracy and human rights, undermining the governments’ credibility and domestic legitimacy and spurring diplomatic, economic and political pressure for change.66 One can hardly make sense of democratization and redemocratization in Eastern Europe and Latin America without reference to the power of normative commitments to democracy and human rights and attention to the ways that these commitments were sustained and strengthened by transnational ties.67 Civil society on the anti-authoritarian model aims to bring about democracy in the face of a hostile regime.68 Its democratic functions and effects are primarily transformational: it seeks the democratization of the regime in co-operation with transnational networks of supporters and the rehabilitation of society through the gradual creation of an independent social sphere of civility. On what assumptions do these strategies for democratization depend? Strangely enough, on the same assumptions as the democratic effects of neo-Tocquevillian civil society. First, while civil society CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 11 functions in opposition to and often in spite of the state, it is still defined (conceptually and empirically) by its relation to the state. Civil society clearly aims at the transformation of a specific state and society – Czech, Polish, Argentinian – for renewal and rehabilitation. Resistance and opposition are directed toward a particular regime or state apparatus and rooted within the political and ethical community of a particular state society. Civil society seeks to create an autonomous sphere independent of the state’s intrusive ideology and bureaucracy, but its social boundaries and membership are still determined by the state. This link between civil society and a particular state is crucial to the strategy of democratization captured in the spiral model of Risse and Sikkink. These movements used traditional statist political measures – political, economic and diplomatic leverage – to press for the reform of authoritarian regimes. These strategies were effective because of the congruity between the targeted traditional states, with their discrete territories, economies and populations, and the democratic civil society movements within them. First, there was something definite to target and the means for doing so were well understood: transnational networks supporting local civil society movements took for granted and relied on the dynamics of realist politics in the Westphalian mould. Second, the objective was also well understood: to create a democratic regime on the social- or liberal-democratic model. Third, external pressure for change was motivated and justified in part by the sense that the targeted regime was neither representative of nor responsive to the will of its citizens. These points tie directly into the second, related assumption concerning the symmetry between civil society and the state. Although this symmetry is a pale echo of the democratic symmetry central to the neo-Tocquevillian model, the transformative aspirations of anti-authoritarian civil society still depend upon the same idea of a community of fate in which members of society are bound together in a shared political destiny. In addition to its role in justifying external pressure, this symmetry is manifest in the social solidarity underlying efforts to resist and ultimately remake the regime. The symmetry is clear in the political and ethical strategies of evolutionism, living in truth, and the parallel polis (itself never realized), which assert that state and society can be transformed through the rehabilitation of their constituent members and the institutions of their daily lives. This programme also represents a backhanded recognition of the mutually constitutive nature of state and civil society: its strategies indicate that not just the government but society itself was corrupted by the penetration of the state’s intrusive ideological and security apparatus.69 The rehabilitation of society requires the rehabilitation of citizens as well as of their governing institutions. It is harder to assess democratic claims for GCS informed by the anti-authoritarian model. This is because the claims themselves are less clear; the model is underspeci-fied globally. Transnational networks do successfully use their moral authority to build support for local opposition groups, raise global awareness of certain issues and exert pressure on IGOs and world leaders. Still, these tactics and the victories won through them do not amount to a coherent programme for transforming global governance, much less to a framework for global democracy. Even if the number and success of such efforts could be increased dramatically they remain primarily 12 DEMOCRATIZATION defensive and ad hoc in nature. Generalities like ‘global transformational politics’ and ‘globalization from below’ might capture the spirit and aspirations of activists and scholars, but they provide few political prescriptions. This is not to denigrate these important efforts or to deny their connection to core democratic values; it is rather to note that they provide an incomplete model for democratizing global governance. Still, we can consider whether the strategies for democratization recommended by the anti-authoritarian model make sense supranationally given the assumptions on which they rest. The first strategy is that captured in the spiral model: transnational support for domestic opposition groups leading to positive transformation of the regime. Several problems arise in applying this strategy to global democratization. First, IGOs are not obviously susceptible to the same kinds of pressure as states. Practically, the close – if antagonistic – relationship between state and civil society on the domestic version of this model was a key factor in leveraging change. Because civil society aimed to transform a particular state, it could work with transnational allies to bring pressure on the state. Economic sanctions are effective against states (if at all) because they have relatively discrete economic systems that can be targeted; diplomatic and political sanctions are effective against states because to states such things matter crucially.70 None of these conditions applies to IGOs (at least not in the same way). They have no economies to punish, no diplomats to isolate. It is of course possible to pressure their officials and the governments who appoint them, but their intergovernmental nature significantly insulates IGOs from the heat of traditional pressure politics. Further, because global governance is highly differentiated – many regimes in many functional domains – bringing sustained and unified pressure on state governments to transform the system of governance (as opposed to changing policy) is difficult. These difficulties relate directly to a second cluster of problems with the transnational pressure strategy. At the state level, unified opposition was called forth by the common experience of systematic and pervasive oppression. This unity helped elicit
  • 4. transnational support in part because it established a democratic impetus and justifi-cation for change. Global governance is more complex; diverse regimes affect differently situated people in very different ways, making democratic solidarity and claims about ‘democratic’ opposition difficult to assess. IGOs do not govern defined political communities; their rule is limited to particular functional domains. There is no political community of fate associated with this form of rule, making it less likely that democratic solidarity of the kind envisioned by the anti-authoritarian model could crystallize. Moreover, the disproportional influence of rich countries in most IGOs means that they often serve the interests of those countries and their citizens, making transnational solidarity problematic. This is not to deny that opposition to particular policies will sometimes be quite strong, especially where their implementation involves violations of human rights. But it is questionable whether such opposition qualifies as global democracy or a global movement for democratization. A politics of democratic opposition seems too simplistic for the complex realities of global governance today. The second major strategy associated with the anti-authoritarian model is rehabilitation, social and political transformation realized through individual ethical CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 13 commitments. This strategy obviously depends on a high degree of symmetry between civil society and the state: Polish opposition groups aimed to transform the Polish state and Polish society. Much of the anti-authoritarian model’s democratic appeal comes from a faith in the political character of individual ethical acts; the hope is that these acts lead to social rehabilitation and renewal and, ultimately, to the regime’s transformation. This hope clearly requires and depends on a strong symmetry between civil society and the targeted regime; otherwise, individual actions could not precipitate political change. The mechanism of transformation envisioned here is tenuous even within states; the empirical link between ‘living in truth’ and regime change is uncertain, but at least involves creating an autonomous space for resistance. This mechanism seems improbable at the global level both because the links between individuals and specific IGOs are less direct and because lack of autonomous political space is not really the problem. The limits of these two strategies at the global level point to two more general difficulties with the anti-authoritarian model of GCS. First, the complexity of global governance makes it unclear what ‘regime’ and ‘regime change’ might mean supranationally – especially since some IGOs, like the UNDP or the nascent ICC, support democratic norms. Total opposition and wholesale transformation seem inappropriately broad and strategically imprudent in this context. Second, given the transformational aims of the anti-authoritarian model, one might well ask transformation to what? The democratic function of the anti-authoritarian model is bringing about a liberal democracy. In the global context this puts the cart before the horse: it is profoundly unclear, as a brief survey of the literature indicates, what a democratic system of global governance might look like or what form it should take – a global state? a federation like the European Union? Being committed to democratic norms, as many agents in GCS no doubt are, is not the same as bringing about democracy. This is a much more vexing problem than advocates of democratizing global governance often appreciate, and it will be revisited shortly. To repeat, the article takes no position with respect to the value, importance or efficacy of transnational network and associational activity: these are not the questions with which the account is concerned. Yet it is not simply repeating cautionary statements about the uncertainty of GCS’s democratic effects. Instead the main proposition is that the purported democratic functions and effects of the two most commonly evoked models for GCS rest on assumptions that do not hold globally. This finding challenges the adequacy and propriety of these models as frameworks for thinking about global democracy and democratization – without prejudicing questions about the role of network and associational activity in creating and sustaining global democracy. Conclusion: The (Epistemological) Problem of Global Democracy My argument to this point can be summarized succinctly. The purported democratic functions and effects of domestic civil society models rely on statist assumptions about politics. These assumptions do not hold for supranational politics, undermining the democratic potential of GCS as a model for global democracy. This conclusion 14 DEMOCRATIZATION argues that these failures reflect broader epistemological problems in the study of global politics, problems that, unless recognized and corrected, will continue to confuse our thinking about global democracy. Arguments proposing GCS as a model for global democracy exhibit what some theorists have called the ‘domestic fallacy’. This fallacy frequently appears in two interrelated misconceptions about global politics and democracy. The first is that the problem of global democracy is primarily a problem of size; the second, that supranational politics is fundamentally similar to domestic politics. These misconceptions lead to mistakes like those we have discovered in democratic arguments for GCS. One critic of GCS arguments has observed that The notion of civil society itself makes little sense apart from the notion of the state against which it was originally articulated as a form of politics contained within its boundaries, a form of domesticity, sometimes public and sometimes private, that depends first and foremost on the capacity of states to carve out the spatial domains necessary for any kind of politics worthy of the name to be constituted.71 The domestic fallacy results from our frequent failure to recognize how deeply our thinking about politics is shaped by and embedded in the conceptual framework of the Westphalian state. Consider first the view that the problem of global democracy is primarily one of size. When we characterize the problem in terms of disjunctures, of a mismatch between an increasingly global politics and existing state-level democratic institutions, this view appears almost natural. Moreover, the solution to the problem, thus conceived, seems straightforward: we should ‘super-size’ existing democratic institutions to ‘fit’ global politics. This is essentially the approach reflected in neo-Tocquevillian thinking about GCS, but it is also evident in cosmopolitan proposals for global assemblies and parliaments. Seeing the problem of global democracy as a problem of size invites two sorts of confusion. The first is confusion of the institutions through which democracy is realized with democracy itself. When we treat global democracy as a problem of size we tend to treat the familiar democratic institutions as ends rather than – as they should be regarded – means of translating democratic principles into practice.72 The second and related confusion is treating the scale and reach of democratic institutions as unrelated to democracy’s meaning and purpose. The territorial limits of modern democratic institutions are not mere contingencies; they are directly related to democracy’s foundational normative assumptions concerning the demos and its sovereignty. Democratic institutions are located where they are in part thanks to historical contingencies, but this history itself informed the theorization of modern democracy.73 The idea of a people whose will is supreme within a particular territory and whose consent legitimizes government follows from the idea that states are natural and appropriate containers of politics – that is, from the idea of sovereignty. Democracy’s territorial institutions reflect this assumption; they are legitimate not because they are representative but because they represent an already constituted people in an already constituted political community. Thus it is impossible to change the scale or reach of democratic institutions without changing the meaning CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 15 of democracy itself. Such conceptual connections get elided when democratic theorists view our role as one of transcribing existing models to the global context, finding plausible ways to make them fit or work globally.74 Equally problematic is the assumption that global politics is fundamentally similar to domestic politics. The anti-authoritarian model illustrates several problems with this assumption, as we have seen, though again such problems apply to proposals for global parliaments and global deliberation as well. Consider here the example of so-called ‘new’ political spaces; despite the adjective, these spaces are treated as identical to traditional political spaces in terms of the politics that will fill them. But these spaces are really new. For one thing, they are politically layered: GCS, for instance, overlays already constituted political spaces without obliterating them. These two conceptual spaces coexist in one geographical space in ways that are unfamiliar and difficult to theorize. Traditional democratic theory is anchored in an exclusive political cartography (the sovereign state) that might be divided (public/private, family/civil, society/state) but is not multilayered.75 Concepts theorized for such a political space are not readily applied to the ‘new medievalism’ of overlapping jurisdictions and loyalties that typify global governance. Governance without government might aptly characterize supranational rule today; democracy without government is more difficult, precisely because modern democratic theory is in large part a theory of government. Since there is no supranational government, and since governance overlaps with and cuts across constituted governments, we have a new theoretical problem, not just a new instance of an old one. Put differently, it is not enough to modify the size or scope of familiar democratic institutions to accommodate new political spaces, overlapping jurisdictions and other such phenomena. To do so presumes their similarity to domestic phenomena by treating the problems they generate as problems of application, obfuscating how they impact the relevance and coherence of existing democratic models and concepts. To see this, consider accountability. It is a widely held view that making global governance regimes more accountable makes them more democratic (or even ‘democratizes’ them). This writer has nothing against accountability: he believes it is a good idea. But accountability to whom? To everyone? Or to those most affected by some issue? How does one determine who is most affected? How does one determine the criteria for making that determination? Who decides that question? The Westphalian state and the theory of sovereignty underlying it, whatever its empirical embarrassments, provided ready-made answers to such questions, answers modern democratic theory has incorporated at the most fundamental level in ideas like the demos and popular sovereignty. Accountability is democratic because it makes governance activities accountable to the right people; who they are is taken for granted. So accountability and similar notions are problematized by globalization not only because we become unsure to whom they pertain but also because, absent a settled conviction about this question, it is not clear that accountability remains democratic or even what ‘democratic’ might mean. These are not merely abstract problems. How does global accountability square with the continued responsiveness of state-level democracy to its people? Do citizens of rich democracies really want the IGOs currently administering the world order in their favour to instead treat the concerns 16 DEMOCRATIZATION of everyone equally? On what democratic basis could they object to such an arrangement – other than one that reasserted the democratic primacy of the national community of fate? Critics might object here that the argument is guilty of the very mistake that has been ascribed to GCS theories – and that the writer has missed his own point. Part of the appeal of proposals for a democratic GCS is that they help us escape this Westphalian mindset. By emphasizing that democracy has worked in a certain way within the state, these critics might assert, the author reinforces the view that it cannot work apart from the state. The author has missed, the critics might continue, that GCS is precisely a way of conceiving how democracy might work outside the state, how it might be deepened and extended into new and emerging domains of governance. His position seems to imply that democracy does require a demos, traditional parliamentary institutions and the other familiar trappings of the state and dynamics of state politics. However, the article’s criticism of GCS theories is not that they fail to appreciate that democracy can only be realized within the state; on the contrary, the author shares a commitment to finding ways to realize democracy globally.76 But democracy as we understand it today was theorized and implemented within the modern state, with two important implications. First, these models cannot simply be applied to global politics without careful consideration of whether their democratic functions and effects can be realized in that context. While GCS theories have been the focus here, many theories of global democracy also neglect this important question. Second – and here is where the imagined objection to the article breaks down – we cannot assume that extricating the concept of democracy from the context in which it was theorized and institutionalized leaves its meaning intact. Our understanding of what democracy is – never mind how it works – is so deeply tied up with its realization in the Westphalian state that we must seriously reconsider even our most basic intuitions about what it might mean apart from that context. The point is not that there can be no democracy without a demos or a parliament; it is instead that we have very little sense of what democracy means once these concepts and institutions cease to correspond with political regularities in the familiar way.
  • 5. Even seemingly unobjectionable notions like accountability prove unreliable and potentially misleading guides to cogent thinking about global democracy. We need a theory of global democracy, not just the application of existing democratic theory to the global context. And we need it urgently, to provide an alternative to the increasingly dominant and anti-democratic logic of neo-liberalism driving contemporary globalization.77 It is crucial to step back and reconsider democracy’s core values, its fundamental principles and commitments, and rethink what they might mean once removed from the conceptual framework of the modern state. Only then will it be possible to make reliable judgements about how we might pursue democratization and realize democratic values. Social movements uniting people around the globe in a shared commitment to democratic norms will form an important part of this pursuit, and the activities of many networks and movements today perform a vital function in keeping the power and promise of that commitment plainly before us. As students of democracy, however, we must avoid the temptation to confuse the CIVIL SOCIETY AND GLOBAL DEMOCRACY 17 democratic potentialities of such activity with global democracy. The most difficult problem of global democracy lies in determining what it might be. But, unavoidably, it is with that problem that we must begin. Civil society is composed of the totality of voluntary civic and social organizations and institutions that form the basis of a functioning society as opposed to the force-backed structures of a state (regardless of that state's political system) and commercial institutions. Origin The term is often traced to Adam Ferguson, who saw the development of a "commercial state" as a way to change the corrupt feudal order and strengthen the liberty of the individual.[1] While Ferguson did not draw a line between the state and the society, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, a German philosopher, made this distinction in his Elements of the Philosophy of Right [2]. In this work, civil society (Hegel used the term "buergerliche Gesellschaft" though it is now referred to as Zivilgesellschaft in German to emphasize a more inclusive community) was a stage on the dialectical relationship between Hegel's perceived opposites, the macro-community of the state and the micro-community of the family [3]. Broadly speaking, the term was split, like Hegel's followers, to the political left and right. On the left, it became the foundation for Karl Marx's bourgeois society [4]; to the right it became a description for all non-state aspects of society, expanding out of the economic rigidity of Marxism into culture, society and politics [5] Definition There are myriad definitions of civil society. The London School of Economics Centre for Civil Society working definition is illustrative: Civil society refers to the arena of uncoerced collective action around shared interests, purposes and values. In theory, its institutional forms are distinct from those of the state, family and market, though in practice, the boundaries between state, civil society, family and market are often complex, blurred and negotiated. Civil society commonly embraces a diversity of spaces, actors and institutional forms, varying in their degree of formality, autonomy and power. Civil societies are often populated by organisations such as registered charities, development non-governmental organisations, community groups, women's organisations, faith-based organisations, professional associations, trade unions, self-help groups, social movements, business associations, coalitions and advocacy groups.[6] Civil society and democracy The literature on links between civil society and democracy have their root in early liberal writings like those of Tocqueville. However they were developed in significant ways by 20th century theorists like Gabriel Almond and Sidney Verba, who identified the role of civil society in a democratic order as vital [7]. They argued that the political element of many civil society organisations facilitates better awareness and a more informed citizenry, who make better voting choices, participate in politics, and hold government more accountable as a result [8]. The statutes of these organizations have often been considered micro-constitutions because they accustom participants to the formalities of democratic decision making. More recently, Robert Putnam has argued that even non-political organisations in civil society are vital for democracy. This is because they build social capital, trust and shared values, which are transferred into the political sphere and help to hold society together, facilitating an understanding of the interconnectedness of society and interests within it Others, however, have questioned how democratic civil society actually is. Some have noted that the civil society actors have now obtained a remarkable amount of political power without anyone directly electing or appointing them [10]. Finally, other scholars have argued that, since the concept of civil society is closely related to democracy and representation, it should in turn be linked with ideas of nationality and nationalism [11]. Civil society and globalization: Global Civil Society The term civil society is currently often used by critics and activists as a reference to sources of resistance to and the domain of social life which needs to be protected against globalization. This is because it is seen as acting beyond boundaries and across different territories [12]. However, as civil society can, under many definitions, include and be funded and directed by those businesses and institutions (especially donors linked to European and Northern states) who support globalization, this is a contested use [13]. On the other hand, others see globalization as a social phenomenon bringing classical liberal values which inevitably lead to a larger role for civil society at the expense of politically derived state institutions. Civil Society's Responses to Globalization By Candido Grzybowski Corporate Watch November 8, 1995 There is no worse slavery than to be deprived of our ability to think, create, and dare in freedom. There is no greater domination than an imposed way of thinking that cannot be challenged. Nothing is more tragic than to be limited by visions, desires and justifications presented to us as inevitable. Globalization is more than a process in human history; it seems to be and to act as a prison for hearts and minds, thoughts and movements. The dominant form of globalization appears as the only way out that nothing could oppose. We are told that anyone who does not adjust to this fate will perish. At least, this is how the concept of globalization has been disseminated by governments, businesspeople, financiers - or their ideologues. We must rebel against this way of thinking. Planetary citizenship requires nonconformist thought and action. The first response to globalization is to acknowledge that it was produced by us, by human beings. It is not a monster to rule over us, but a human invention, with its limitations and possibilities like our own life condition. We must use a different approach to think about globalization, taking alternative globalizations into consideration. For this, the conventional hegemonic way of thinking dictated by neoliberalism and by "free market" consensus is not very helpful. It is necessary that we, as citizens of the planet earth committed to democracy, build our own agenda, our own way of viewing issues and tasks, our own priorities. We can't ignore other approaches and their proposals, but let's not limit ourselves to them. Let's face up to them! Several globalizations, different responses Dominant forms of globalization are powered by an unrestrained drive to maximize profits. Open the borders, reduce and privatize the state, deregulate, be efficient and competitive, submit everything and everybody to savage free market law - such are the rules and basic principles of key economic globalization actors. In practice, global speculation was installed - a global casino. Productive structures and processes are increasingly more distanced from human development needs. Such globalization entails huge economic instability and political crisis. It is deeply destructive and antihuman. Never before has social inequality and exclusion reached such levels - too many human beings for an economy meant for less people, pursuing an unsustainable pattern of resource-use and consumption. Without borders, apartheid becomes global. In the face of this exclusionary globalization, we need to look at other globalizations. Some of them bear alternatives and hopes. In the struggle against globalization serving only business interests, actors emerge who are forging the bases of a planetary civil society founded on human rights and active citizenship. However, fundamentalisms of all sorts also proliferate in civil societies, propagating intolerance and violence. They destroy and exclude in their own ways. The key is that ongoing processes are challenging the world power system formed in the past. National states have been weakened and have been losing their regulatory capacity over economic forces active on a world scale. However, multilateral agencies are still deeply influenced by their origins and need many changes to confront challenges posed by globalization processes. In fact, the break with a bipolar world - with its hegemonic models and peripheries - does not just signal the victory of one pole over the other. It aggravates world contrasts within each particular society and within all humanity . However different we find ourselves, our destiny is also connected to others. Globalization processes do not remove us from where we live, from our culture, nation, or religion. They simply change the bases and perspectives of our lives, of our way of thinking and acting. Because our localized action can have substantial global impact, global dynamics - operating outside our control - redefines the possibilities and limits of what we do at a local level. More than ever we must "think globally and act locally." We live amidst very confusing proposals and concrete struggles. More than a new world order, we witness an extremely contradictory process of destruction and construction of a new civilization. Humanity goes through a period of uncertainties, lack of definitions, and absence of great utopian projects pointing the way forward. The task is precisely to rebuild such projects on new bases. We need to put forward globalization alternatives that could subject the market and state power to world citizens' demands. Priority task: strengthen civil society's democratic outlook Fundamental changes in humankind's history may occur along with economic or power changes. However, this doesn't imply that economic and power change should be the exclusive and priority focus of the strategy for change and for building a different globalization. Rather, it is a necessary, but not sufficient condition. After all, who makes up the economy and state power? Genetically, we ourselves do. The very human condition of living in society leads us to invent economic and power structures. Neither economies nor states create civil societies, just the opposite. With this approach, I have to acknowledge that civil society's most strategic and fundamental response to globalization is to reinvent itself. Civil societies must view themselves in the framework of globalization, enabling each inhabitant to think about himself or herself as a member of the same planet earth. Above all, we members of civil societies must redefine ourselves as citizens of a globalized world. This is a greater task than would appear at first sight. In fact, I'm saying that cultural change within civil society is an indispensable condition for changing the economy and markets, as well as power and state. I understand cultural change as change in ways of thinking and doing by different social actors making up a given society in a determined historical framework. Fortunately, this is not a vague and distant concept, but something concrete within everyone's reach. I'm referring to real processes in our societies and at the international level which merit and should have our attention here and now. Identifying such processes, acting on them, and maximizing their democratizing possibilities is our most urgent priority. I will mention some clear-cut examples. The environmental movement has a potential for cultural change that I want to emphasize. Today we view our relationship with nature in a radically different way. This results from an approach to environmental degradation and to challenges posed by sustainability forged by certain citizens' groups in concrete and specific situations. Their capacity to identify issues, formulate proposals, and mobilize - thus creating the first large global movement - has become one of the most insurmountable barriers to economic globalization. Raising awareness, public debate, and concrete action against corporations and governments has created the possibility of re-thinking the development model itself. Is this enough? No, but without the environmental movement, civil society would be deprived of a fundamental instrument to come to grips with globalization imposed by free-market apologists. Still on the ecological movement, it's important to note how it interconnects global and local aspects. I can cite the example of Brazil's rubber-tappers and forest peoples. They have mobilized and started fighting to defend their immediate living and working conditions threatened by forest destruction to create pastures and set up large farming and cattle-raising projects. Ecological groups throughout the world have identified the global dimension in their struggle as an alternative to environmental destruction carried out by prevailing economic processes. The symbolic character of this struggle internationalized it and the murder of Chico Mendes was perceived as an assault upon planetary citizenry. Using the same approach, the feminist movement is rethinking gender relations and the women's condition throughout the world. The past twenty years, culminating in the recent Beijing conference, has witnessed the emergence of an issue that remains one of civil society's greatest challenges. After all, both the problem and its solution are found in civil society before new power and production relationships materialize. We are facing a process of cultural change in gender relations, barely underway, but indispensable to radical change and effective democratization of human societies. The extremely diverse process already underway in civil societies throughout the planet bears great potentialities for building another kind of globalization. I'm citing these examples to show the importance of change in civil society itself, as a precondition for other forms of globalization. I should also acknowledge the existence within civil societies of great obstacles and limiting forces to the alternative of global democratization. Religiously and/or ethnically-inspired fundamentalist movements have prospered because they attract followers and activists in our own societies. It's not cultural diversity that explains fundamentalism's destructive potential to create violence and social exclusion. On the contrary, non-acceptance of equality in diversity leads to isolation, fragmentation, and intolerance. It's in the hands of civil society's groups to build conditions to defy fundamentalism as a world vision and to confront its destructive practices. Above all, it's a confrontation among citizens. Israeli Prime Minister's recent murder in the conflict-ridden Middle East reveals the nature of the fundamentalist problem. However, our civil societies face great challenges on the issue of poverty and social exclusion. Globalization processes may also be seen to unveil and deepen the logic of inequality and exclusion in the world. Sparing no society, poverty and destitution are now global phenomena. Worse still, there is a radical separation between economic and social spheres - while economies are globalized, the social is nationalized. The greatest indicator of the narrow limits of economic globalization is increasing control over migration. All barriers to circulation of goods are lifted but their producers are blocked from moving freely! In addition, visions and wills are forged within societies to exclude foreign workers, denying them basic citizenship rights. These are globalization's contrasts and dead ends. In Brazil we have a movement that is particularly eloquent in showing potentialities for cultural change, forged by civil society itself around the issue of social exclusion and poverty. It has a universal dimension despite its unique Brazilian features. It joins with other similar movements throughout the world and contributes in its own way to forging a new way of thinking and acting by groups of civil society relating to business and government. After all, it appeals to citizens' consciousness and action as the basis for change. We are referring to the movement "Citizens' Action Against Hunger, Poverty, and for Life" (Citizens' Action). Since March 1993, Citizens' Action has, through successive mobilizations, forced society to look introspectively for ideas and energy to launch a process to alter the country's hunger and poverty situation. This article is not the place to describe that civic movement. It just draws attentions to its nature. The movement is a learning process for the citizenry based on ethical indignation. Citizens' Action was not created to remind the poor and the hungry that they are responsible for their own fate. This movement directs itself to those with means, to those integrated in the current development model, to enable them to see the others and assume responsibility as citizens for their fate. Thus, basic values of human togetherness, the foundation of democracy, are recovered. It's not a matter of struggling for one's own rights, but for citizenship rights denied to the hungry, the destitute, and the excluded of all sorts. Denying the citizenship of others limits ours. Democracy and misery are ethically incompatible. In Citizens' Action there is no denying the importance of the state, governments and their policies, nor corporations' social responsibility. However, we seek the catapult for change that comes from citizens changing their attitudes when confronted with this issue. They can, in a sovereign way and without asking anyone's opinion, invent, take initiatives, organize decentralized committees - without duplicating models. They can mobilize forces and resources, promote partnerships, and contribute their share. Such actions create the atmosphere for a political and cultural movement favoring change. The lesson to draw from Brazil's Citizens' Action is that the potential in civil society for change is huge and decisive but needs to be primed. A question worth noticing is the emergence of ethics in civil societies' response to the neoliberal outlook and its globalization proposals. Mere defense of a human society based on free market laws condemns us to barbarism. Its destructive social and ecological potential results from denying primacy to values or to ethical considerations in relationships between human beings and between peoples. Even worse, this is a cynical way of thinking because it denies any possibility of an alternative approach. Dubbing itself as modern, this deeply conservative thinking invites each society in particular and the planetary society under construction to renounce the possibility of advancing civilization. Neoliberal thought is authoritarian and technocratic, prioritizing the economy to the detriment of politics and culture. Humankind had to struggle and suffer to identify and uphold values and rights whose central role is now negated by this narrow-minded utilitarianism. To see beyond the neoliberal wave and re-affirm the primacy of ethics and human beings is one of the greatest challenges for humanists and democrats on the threshold of the XXI Century. Forging another kind of globalization within civil society is possible. To do that we must re-affirm the primacy of the ethical principles constituting democracy: equality, freedom, participation, and human diversity and solidarity. They are capable of touching the hearts and minds of civil society's different groups and sectors. These principles should regulate power and market and be upheld and practiced throughout the world. The priority task is to counterpose a deepening process of global democracy and of planetary-scale cultural change to worldwide neoliberal disorder. A viable strategy: combining social mobilization and political pressure Having explained that the basic proposal is viable, let's tentatively discuss the strategy as a whole. We live in a concrete world, within
  • 6. time and space, with ongoing real processes. We want to shape globalization taking into account that it may open new possibilities for humankind. This is not only desirable but necessary. But how can civil society redirect globalization's course? The strategy I propose is to prioritize ways of viewing and thinking - the prevailing attitudes and values within civil societies themselves concerning globalization. Perceptions and proposals of different civic groups, their movements and large mobilizations are forged in political and cultural confrontation and through action and public debate. To get the other side of the proposal to work - pressure, lobbying, and demands on governments, multilateral agencies and corporations - it is necessary to create a favorable atmosphere for linkages and networks within civil society, at both the national and international level. This is not the place to analyze the ample openings for political action by different actors in the planetary civil society being built today. We all have shown already that, when based on concrete local mobilizations, our intervention in negotiating forums such as large international conferences changes the quality of negotiations, both in their content and in the type of commitments governments undertake in those events. We also realize that conferences are only a starting point. Carrying out action plans requires new pressures and lobbying efforts. Again, broader engagement of different social sectors and a favorable atmosphere become decisive factors. Therefore, our strategy must combine actions and proposals to strengthen and mobilize civil society, and efforts to urge governments and multilateral agencies to take the pathway already indicated on the international agenda. The official agenda should not set the limits of our action. We need to expand our independent spaces for political action, with our own agenda, even at the international level. NGO and social movements' conferences, debates, forums, and networks (including computer networks) should help in the task of emancipating societies, of providing them with autonomy and capacity for exercising their role. In formulating globalization proposals we must free ourselves from narrow national and local outlooks and from the hegemony of governments, multilateral agencies, large corporations and finance capital. Although we don't shy away from this arena of struggle, the possibility of our intervention at this level does not only depend on competence and creativity. Above all, political action to confront the power system and the market for a democratic globalization presupposes strengthening our civil societies. Our challenge is to combine both poles. This confrontation will certainly shape a different globalization. CHAPTER 2 THE FIVE STAGES-OF-GROWTH--A SUMMARY It is possible to identify all societies, in their economic dimensions, as lying within one of five categories: the traditional society, the preconditions for take-off, the take-off, the drive to maturity, and the age of high mass-consumption. THE TRADITIONAL SOCIETY First, the traditional society. A traditional society is one whose structure is developed within limited production functions, based on pre-Newtonian science and technology, and on pre-Newtonian attitudes towards the physical world. Newton is here used as a symbol for that watershed in history when men came widely to believe that the external world was subject to a few knowable laws, and was systematically capable of productive manipulation. The conception of the traditional society is, however, in no sense static; and it would not exclude increases in output. Acreage could be expanded; some ad hoc technical innovations, often highly productive innovations, could be introduced in trade, industry and agriculture; productivity could rise with, for example, the improvement of irrigation works or the discovery and diffusion of a new crop. But the central fact about the traditional society was that a ceiling existed on the level of attainable output per head. This ceiling resulted from the fact that the potentialities which flow from modern science and technology were either not available or not regularly and systematically applied. Both in the longer past and in recent times the story of traditional societies was thus a story of endless change. The area and volume of trade within them and between them fluctuated, for example, with the degree of political and social turbulence, the efficiency of central rule, the upkeep of the roads. Population--and, within limits, the level of life--rose and fell not only with the sequence of the harvests, but with the incidence of war and of plague. Varying degrees of manufacture developed; but, as in agriculture, the level of productivity was limited by the inaccessibility of modern science, its applications, and its frame of mind. Generally speaking, these societies, because of the limitation on productivity, had to devote a very high proportion of their resources to agriculture; and flowing from the agricultural system there was an hierarchical social structure, with relatively narrow scope--but some scope--for vertical mobility. Family and clan connexions played a large role in social organization. The value system of these societies was generally geared to what might be called a long-run fatalism; that is, the assumption that the range of possibilities open to one's grandchildren would be just about what it had been for one's grandparents. But this long-run fatalism by no means excluded the short-run option that, within a considerable range, it was possible and legitimate for the individual to strive to improve his lot, within his lifetime. In Chinese villages, for example, there was an endless struggle to acquire or to avoid losing land, yielding a situation where land rarely remained within the same family for a century. Although central political rule--in one form or another--often existed in traditional societies, transcending the relatively self-sufficient regions, the centre of gravity of political power generally lay in the regions, in the hands of those who owned or controlled the land. The landowner maintained fluctuating but usually profound influence over such central political power as existed, backed by its entourage of civil servants and soldiers, imbued with attitudes and controlled by interests transcending the regions. In terms of history then, with the phrase 'traditional society' we are grouping the whole pre-Newtonian world : the dynasties in China; the civilization of the Middle East and the Mediterranean; the world of medieval Europe. And to them we add the post-Newtonian societies which, for a time, remained untouched or unmoved by man's new capability for regularly manipulating his environment to his economic advantage. To place these infinitely various, changing societies in a single category, on the ground that they all shared a ceiling on the productivity of their economic techniques, is to say very little indeed. But we are, after all, merely clearing the way in order to get at the subject of this book; that is, the post-traditional societies, in which each of the major characteristics of the traditional society was altered in such ways as to permit regular growth: its politics, social structure, and (to a degree) its values, as well as its economy. THE PRECONDITIONS FOR TAKE-OFF The second stage of growth embraces societies in the process of transition; that is, the period when the preconditions for take-off are developed; for it takes time to transform a traditional society in the ways necessary for it to exploit the fruits of modern science, to fend off diminishing returns, and thus to enjoy the blessings and choices opened up by the march of compound interest. The preconditions for take-off were initially developed, in a clearly marked way, in Western Europe of the late seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries as the insights of modern science began to be translated into new production functions in both agriculture and industry, in a setting given dynamism by the lateral expansion of world markets and the international competition for them. But all that lies behind the break-up of the Middle Ages is relevant to the creation of the preconditions for take-off in Western Europe. Among the Western European states, Britain, favoured by geography, natural resources, trading possibilities, social and political structure, was the first to develop fully the preconditions for take-off. The more general case in modern history, however, saw the stage of preconditions arise not endogenously but from some external intrusion by more advanced societies. These invasions-literal or figurative-shocked the traditional society and began or hastened its undoing; but they also set in motion ideas and sentiments which initiated the process by which a modern alternative to the traditional society was constructed out of the old culture. The idea spreads not merely that economic progress is possible, hut that economic progress is a necessary condition for some other purpose, judged to be good: be it national dignity, private profit, the general welfare, or a better life for the children. Education, for some at least, broadens and changes to suit the needs of modern economic activity. New types of enterprising men come forward--in the private economy, in government, or both--willing to mobilize savings and to take risks in pursuit of profit or modernization. Banks and other institutions for mobilizing capital appear. Investment increases, notably in transport, communications, and in raw materials in which other nations may have an economic interest. The scope of commerce, internal and external, widens. And, here and there, modern manufacturing enterprise appears, using the new methods. But all this activity proceeds at a limited pace within an economy and a society still mainly characterized by traditional low-productivity methods, by the old social structure and values, and by the regionally based political institutions that developed in conjunction with them. In many recent cases, for example, the traditional society persisted side by side with modern economic activities, conducted for limited economic purposes by a colonial or quasi-colonial power. Although the period of transition--between the traditional society and the take-off--saw major changes in both the economy itself and in the balance of social values, a decisive feature was often political. Politically, the building of an effective centralized national state--on the basis of coalitions touched with a new nationalism, in opposition to the traditional landed regional interests, the colonial power, or both, was a decisive aspect of the preconditions period; and it was, almost universally, a necessary condition for take-off. There is a great deal more that needs to be said about the preconditions period, but we shall leave it for chapter 3, where the anatomy of the transition from a traditional to a modern society is examined. THE TAKE-OFF We come now to the great watershed in the life of modern societies: the third stage in this sequence, the take-off. The take-off is the interval when the old blocks and resistances to steady growth are finally overcome. The forces making for economic progress, which yielded limited bursts and enclaves of modern activity, expand and come to dominate the society. Growth becomes its normal condition. Compound interest becomes built, as it were, into its habits and institutional structure. In Britain and the well-endowed parts of the world populated substantially from Britain (the United States, Canada etc.) the proximate stimulus for take-off was mainly (but not wholly) technological. In the more general case, the take-off awaited not only the build-up of social overhead capital and a surge of technological development in industry and agriculture, but also the emergence to political power of a group prepared to regard the modernization of the economy as serious, high-order political business. During the take-off, the rate of effective investment and savings may rise from, say, 5 % of the national income to 10% or more; although where heavy social overhead capital investment was required to create the technical preconditions for take-off the investment rate in the preconditions period could be higher than 5%, as, for example, in Canada before the 1890's and Argentina before 1914. In such cases capital imports usually formed a high proportion of total investment in the preconditions period and sometimes even during the take-off itself, as in Russia and Canada during their pre-1914 railway booms. During the take-off new industries expand rapidly, yielding profits a large proportion of which are reinvested in new plant; and these new industries, in turn, stimulate, through their rapidly expanding requirement for factory workers, the services to support them, and for other manufactured goods, a further expansion in urban areas and in other modern industrial plants. The whole process of expansion in the modern sector yields an increase of income in the hands of those who not only save at high rates but place their savings at the disposal of those engaged in modern sector activities. The new class of entrepreneurs expands; and it directs the enlarging flows of investment in the private sector. The economy exploits hitherto unused natural resources and methods of production. New techniques spread in agriculture as well as industry, as agriculture is commercialized, and increasing numbers of farmers are prepared to accept the new methods and the deep changes they bring to ways of life. The revolutionary changes in agricultural productivity are an essential condition for successful take-off; for modernization of a society increases radically its bill for agricultural products. In a decade or two both the basic structure of the economy and the social and political structure of the society are transformed in such a way that a steady rate of growth can be, thereafter, regularly sustained. As indicated in chapter 4, one can approximately allocate the take-off of Britain to the two decades after 1783; France and the United States to the several decades preceding 1860; Germany, the third quarter of the nineteenth century; Japan, the fourth quarter of the nineteenth century; Russia and Canada the quarter-century or so preceding 1914; while during the 1950's India and China have, in quite different ways, launched their respective take-offs. THE DRIVE TO MATURITY After take-off there follows a long interval of sustained if fluctuating progress, as the now regularly growing economy drives to extend modern technology over the whole front of its economic activity. Some 10-20% of the national income is steadily invested, permitting output regularly to outstrip the increase in population. The make-up of the economy changes unceasingly as technique improves, new industries accelerate, older industries level off. The economy finds its place in the international economy: goods formerly imported are produced at home; new import requirements develop, and new export commodities to match them. The society makes such terms as it will with the requirements of modern efficient production, balancing off the new against the older values and institutions, or revising the latter in such ways as to support rather than to retard the growth process. Some sixty years after take-off begins (say, forty years after the end of take-off) what may be called maturity is generally attained. The economy, focused during the take-off around a relatively narrow complex of industry and technology, has extended its range into more refined and technologically often more complex processes; for example, there may be a shift in focus from the coal, iron, and heavy engineering industries of the railway phase to machine-tools, chemicals, and electrical equipment. This, for example, was the transition through which Germany, Britain, France, and the United States had passed by the end of the nineteenth century or shortly thereafter. But there are other sectoral patterns which have been followed in the sequence from take-off to maturity, which are considered in chapter 5. Formally, we can define maturity as the stage in which an economy demonstrates the capacity to move beyond the original industries which powered its take-off and to absorb and to apply efficiently over a very wide range of its resources--if not the whole range--the most advanced fruits of (then) modern technology. This is the stage in which an economy demonstrates that it has the technological and entrepreneurial skills to produce not everything, but anything that it chooses to produce. It may lack (like contemporary Sweden and Switzerland, for example) the raw materials or other supply conditions required to produce a given type of output economically; but its dependence is a matter of economic choice or political priority rather than a technological or institutional necessity. Historically, it would appear that something like sixty years was required to move a society from the beginning of take-off to maturity. Analytically the explanation for some such interval may lie in the powerful arithmetic of compound interest applied to the capital stock, combined with the broader consequences for a society's ability to absorb modern technology of three successive generations living under a regime where growth is the normal condition. But, clearly, no dogmatism is justified about the exact length of the interval from take-off to maturity. THE AGE OF HIGH MASS-CONSUMPTION We come now to the age of high mass-consumption, where, in time, the leading sectors shift towards durable consumers' goods and services: a phase from which Americans are beginning to emerge; whose not unequivocal joys Western Europe and Japan are beginning energetically to probe; and with which Soviet society is engaged in an uneasy flirtation. As societies achieved maturity in the twentieth century two things happened: real income per head rose to a point where a large number of persons gained a command over consumption which transcended basic food, shelter, and clothing; and the structure of the working force changed in ways which increased not only the proportion of urban to total population, but also the proportion of the population working in offices or in skilled factory jobs-aware of and anxious to acquire the consumption fruits of a mature economy. In addition to these economic changes, the society ceased to accept the further extension of modern technology as an overriding objective. It is in this post-maturity stage, for example, that, through the political process, Western societies have chosen to allocate increased resources to social welfare and security. The emergence of the welfare state is one manifestation of a society's moving beyond technical maturity; but it is also at this stage that resources tend increasingly to be directed to the production of consumers' durables and to the diffusion of services on a mass basis, if consumers' sovereignty reigns. The sewing-machine, the bicycle, and then the various electric-powered household gadgets were gradually diffused. Historically, however, the decisive element has been the cheap mass automobile with its quite revolutionary effects--social as well as economic--on the life and expectations of society. For the United States, the turning point was, perhaps, Henry Ford's moving assembly line of 1913-14; but it was in the 1920's, and again in the post-war decade, 1946-56, that this stage of growth was pressed to, virtually, its logical conclusion. In the 1950's Western Europe and Japan appear to have fully entered this phase, accounting substantially for a momentum in their economies quite unexpected in the immediate post-war years. The Soviet Union is technically ready for this stage, and, by every sign, its citizens hunger for it; but Communist leaders face difficult political and social problems of adjustment if this stage is launched. BEYOND CONSUMPTION Beyond, it is impossible to predict, except perhaps to observe that Americans, at least, have behaved in the past decade as if diminishing relative marginal utility sets in, after a point, for durable consumers' goods; and they have chosen, at the margin, larger families-behaviour in the pattern of Buddenbrooks dynamics.*